Critics of antidiscrimination law have long lamented that the Supreme Court is devoted to a shallow, formal version of equality that fails to account for substantive inequities and stands in the way of affirmative efforts to remediate systemic injustice. But these criticisms are primarily focused on the Supreme Court’s interpretations of race discrimination law. The Court’s most recent foray into statutory sex discrimination law, Bostock v. Clayton County, employed formalistic reasoning to move the law in an expansive direction, interpreting Title VII’s sex discrimination provision to prohibit discrimination against lesbian, gay, and transgender employees. Examining post-Bostock developments, this Article asks whether formal equality might have more potential to advance civil rights than previously thought. It argues that “formal equality” is not a single legal inquiry; rather, in practice, it takes the form of at least three distinct tests. These tests lead to different results in different sex discrimination controversies, such as whether it is discrimination to treat someone adversely for being bisexual or nonbinary; to single out pregnancy, menstruation, breasts, or other aspects of reproductive biology for disparate treatment; to enforce sex-specific dress codes; to exclude transgender people from restrooms consistent with their gender identities; to ban gender-affirming health care; or to restrict who can change the sex designations on their identity documents. Although no formal test neatly maps onto prevailing normative theories and sociological insights about what discrimination is, in recent cases, courts have used formal tests to achieve results consistent with those theories. This account suggests that, rather than insisting that courts adopt substantive tests, civil rights scholars might reconsider the virtues of formalism.
“Equality, in the abstract, has no limits; it is forever demanding to be carried to its ultimate logical conclusions.”1 1.Kenneth L. Karst, The Supreme Court, 1976 Term—Foreword: Equal Citizenship Under the Fourteenth Amendment, 91 Harv. L. Rev. 1, 39 (1977).Show More
Introduction
The law of race discrimination is mired in what critics call “formal equality”: an ahistorical, decontextualized vision of equality law that ignores the social, economic, and political realities of systemic racial inequality and treats affirmative action as the moral equivalent of 1950s-style segregation.2 2.See, e.g., Ian Haney-López, Intentional Blindness, 87 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 1779, 1784 (2012) (“[D]iscriminatory intent doctrine excludes evidence of continued discrimination against non-Whites rooted in history, contemporary practices, and social science . . . . Meanwhile, . . . colorblindness similarly closes courthouse doors to evidence showing that state actors sometimes use race to break down inequality and to foster integration.”); Reva Siegel, Why Equal Protection No Longer Protects: The Evolving Forms of Status-Enforcing State Action, 49 Stan. L. Rev. 1111, 1113 (1997) (criticizing “[c]ontemporary equal protection law” because it “is premised on a formal and historically static conception of ‘discrimination’” focused on “classification” or “discriminatory purpose—a concept the Court has defined as tantamount to malice”).Show More As a result, antidiscrimination scholars are almost uniformly scornful of formal equality, proposing that it be replaced with more substantive definitions of discrimination attuned to context;3 3.See, e.g., Haney-López, supranote 2, at1876 (proposing a “contextual intent” test).Show More social, historical, and cultural meanings;4 4.See, e.g., Issa Kohler-Hausmann, Eddie Murphy and the Dangers of Counterfactual Causal Thinking About Detecting Racial Discrimination, 113 Nw. U. L. Rev. 1163, 1166, 1172 (2019) (arguing for a definition that accounts for “the system of social meanings or practices” that constitute social categories such as race and sex); Charles R. Lawrence III, The Id, the Ego, and Equal Protection: Reckoning with Unconscious Racism, 39 Stan. L. Rev. 317, 355–56 (1987) (proposing a “cultural meaning” test that “would evaluate governmental conduct to see if it conveys a symbolic message to which the culture attaches racial significance” and “considering evidence regarding the historical and social context in which the decision was made and effectuated”).Show More systemic and accumulated group-based disadvantages;5 5.See, e.g., Richard Thompson Ford, Bias in the Air: Rethinking Employment Discrimination Law, 66 Stan. L. Rev. 1381, 1384 (2014) (“[T]he law should replace the conceptually elusive goal of eliminating discrimination with the more concrete goal of requiring employers, government officials, and other powerful actors to meet a duty of care to avoid unnecessarily perpetuating social segregation or hierarchy.”); Siegel, supranote 2, at1146 (suggesting that equal protection doctrine might require scrutiny for “facially neutral policies” that “perpetuate, or aggravate, historic patterns of race and gender inequality”).Show More or “costs and benefits of alternative proposals in each specific setting.”6 6.See, e.g., R. Richard Banks, Class and Culture: The Indeterminacy of Nondiscrimination, 5 Stan. J. C.R. & C.L. 1, 3 (2009) (“[W]e should approach race-related policy disputes in a pragmatic manner, weighing the costs and benefits of alternative proposals in each specific setting.”).Show More
By contrast to the atrophy of race discrimination law through formalism, the law of sex discrimination seems relatively vibrant. In its landmark decision in Bostock v. Clayton County, the Roberts Court ruled that discrimination on the basis of “sex” under Title VII of the Civil Rights Act includes discrimination against lesbian, gay, and transgender workers.7 7.140 S. Ct. 1731, 1737 (2020).Show More But that decision’s reasoning is not based in any sort of contextual or historically grounded understanding of gender-based subordination.8 8.Id.at 1750–51 (denying the relevance of history and pointing out that “applying protective laws to groups that were politically unpopular at the time of the law’s passage—whether prisoners in the 1990s or homosexual and transgender employees in the 1960s—often may be seen as unexpected”).Show More Rather, it relied on a formal, sterile, individualistic concept of “but-for” causation—“if changing the employee’s sex would have yielded a different choice by the employer—a statutory violation has occurred.”9 9.Id. at 1741.Show More Thus, if an employer would not fire a woman for being attracted to men, that employer may not fire a man for being attracted to men.10 10.Id. The same argument works for the transgender employees—for example, a transgender woman may not be penalized for having traits that would be acceptable in an employee who was assigned female at birth. Id.Show More Lower courts have extended Bostock to new contexts, holding, for example, that it requires that schools allow transgender children to use restrooms consistent with their gender identities,11 11.See, e.g., infraSubsection II.A.1 (discussing Grimm v. Gloucester County School Board, 972 F.3d 586, 616, 619 (4th Cir. 2020) (affirming summary judgment in favor of a transgender plaintiff on equal protection and Title IX claims), cert. denied, 141 S. Ct. 2878 (2021)).Show More forbids an employer from firing an employee because her tampon triggered a security scanner,12 12.SeeinfraSubsection II.A.2 (discussing Flores v. Virginia Department of Corrections, No. 20-cv-00087, 2021 WL 668802, at *6 (W.D. Va. Feb. 22, 2021) (denying summary judgment in a sex discrimination case in which an employee was fired when her tampon set off a security scanner triggering the false suspicion that she was smuggling contraband)).Show More and bars schools from imposing dress codes requiring girls to wear skirts.13 13.See, e.g., infraSubsection II.A.1 (discussing Peltier v. Charter Day School, Inc., 37 F.4th 104 (4th Cir. 2021) (en banc) (affirming grant of summary judgment to plaintiffs on § 1983 equal protection claim and reversing grant of summary judgment to school on Title IX claim challenging discriminatory dress code)).Show More
This Article argues that Bostock’s but-for test is an example of a broader phenomenon that it describes as “sex discrimination formalism”: attempts to define intentional sex discrimination according to formal, abstract, logical tests, minimizing consideration of social realities and normative values.14 14.I define discrimination formalism more precisely infra Section I.A. Cf.Morton J. Horwitz, The Transformation of American Law, 1780–1860, at 254 (1977) (discussing “legal formalism” as “an intellectual system which gave common law rules the appearance of being self-contained, apolitical, and inexorable, and which, by making ‘legal reasoning seem like mathematics,’ conveyed ‘an air . . . of . . . inevitability’ about legal decisions”). I do not suggest formal rules succeed at perfect abstraction or constraint; formalism is a matter of degree. See, e.g., Cass R. Sunstein, Must Formalism Be Defended Empirically?, 66 U. Chi. L. Rev. 636, 640 (1999) (“The real question is ‘what degree of formalism?’ rather than ‘formalist or not?’”).Show More It identifies and examines abstract tests used by courts to determine what types of reasons count as intentional sex discrimination in various constitutional and statutory contexts and assesses how those tests work in particular cases. Contrary to the consensus view among civil rights scholars that formalism is anathema to equality,15 15.See, e.g.,supranotes 2, 4, 6 and accompanying text. But cf.Mary Anne Case,“The Very Stereotype the Law Condemns”: Constitutional Sex Discrimination Law as a Quest for Perfect Proxies, 85 Cornell L. Rev. 1447, 1448–52 (2000) (characterizing equal protection cases on sex as standing for the formalistic rule that, when a law, on its face, treats men and women differently, it may not be based on a generalization that would be untrue for even a single individual man or woman, and arguing that, if courts took this rule seriously, it would lead “in interesting and radical directions” like marriage equality).Show More this Article argues that recent cases relying on formal tests have expanded the reach of sex discrimination law to forms of gender inequality overlooked in the past.
One contribution of this Article is to offer a typology of formal tests of disparate treatment. Much scholarship on discrimination law assumes that there are only two modes for thinking about equality: formal and substantive, and that all formal rules are the same.16 16.See, e.g.,Guy-Uriel E. Charles & Luis Fuentes-Rohwer, Pathological Racism, Chronic Racism & Targeted Universalism, 109 Calif. L. Rev. 1107, 1111 (2021) (discussing the “standard doctrinal account,” which lumps together concerns about formal equality and anticlassification in equal protection law);cf.Aziz Z. Huq, What Is Discriminatory Intent?, 103 Cornell L. Rev. 1211, 1223–24 (2018) (“Questions of how discriminatory intent is defined and proved tend to be ancillary and subordinate to a larger critique of the ideological orientation of the doctrine.”).Show More This Article argues there are at least three distinct types of formal rules when it comes to intentional sex discrimination: (1) but-for causation, which asks whether mistreatment would have befallen an individual if their sex were different; (2) anticlassification rules, also referred to as “blindness,”17 17.This is a problematic metaphor, for, among other reasons, the fact that blind people do see race. See generally Osagie Obasogie, Blinded by Sight: Seeing Race Through the Eyes of the Blind (2013).Show More which ask whether a decision-maker acted pursuant to an explicit or implicit policy that considers sex; and (3) “similarly situated” rules, which forbid decision-makers from treating individuals of different sexes who are alike in all relevant respects differently. Importantly, these heuristics for determining discriminatory intent do not require proof of the specific motives of discriminators.18 18.Cf.Pers. Adm’r v. Feeney, 442 U.S. 256, 279 (1979) (“‘Discriminatory purpose’ . . . implies that the decisionmaker . . . selected or reaffirmed a particular course of action at least in part ‘because of,’ not merely ‘in spite of,’ its adverse effects upon an identifiable group.”).Show More While ostensibly aimed at discerning the same core phenomenon—discriminatory intent—these tests have taken on lives of their own in the case law as independent legal “theories” or “claims.” They most often point to the same result, but in a subset of difficult cases, the choice of formal rule can change the outcome. For example, one district judge, a Republican appointee, concluded that Bostock’s but-for test would not count discrimination on the basis of bisexuality as sex discrimination, but an anticlassification inquiry that requires decisions that are “blind” to sex would.19 19.Bear Creek Bible Church v. EEOC, 571 F. Supp. 3d 571, 622 (N.D. Tex. 2021) (concluding that an employer who discriminates on the basis of bisexuality is not discriminating on the basis of sex under “[t]he traditional but-for ‘favoritism’ analyses,” but is failing to act in a way that is “‘blind’ to sex”), vacated sub nom. Braidwood Mgmt., Inc. v. EEOC, 70 F.4th 914, 940 (5th Cir. 2023). Ideology is unlikely to be the explanation for this twist in reasoning. The district court judge, Reed O’Connor, was appointed by President George W. Bush, and is known for striking down the policies of the Biden and Obama administrations. Tierney Sneed, Judge Notorious for Anti-Obamacare Rulings Has Another Crack, CNN (Jan. 28, 2022, 7:56 AM), https://www.cnn.com/2022/01/28/politics/obamacare-reed-oconnor-biden-doj-health/index.html [https://perma.cc/H3G3-TMDH].Show More
Another contribution of this Article is to offer an assessment of the reach of these various formal tests, relevant to next-generation sex discrimination disputes. While scholars have debated the theoretical potential of Bostock’s but-for inquiry,20 20.CompareKatie Eyer, The But-For Theory of Anti-Discrimination Law, 107 Va. L. Rev. 1621, 1624–25 (2021) (applauding the but-for theory on the ground that it clarifies disparate treatment law and avoids the intent requirement), withRobin Dembroff & Issa Kohler-Hausmann, Supreme Confusion About Causality at the Supreme Court, 25 CUNY L. Rev. 57, 58 (2022) (arguing thatBostock’s but-for test is incoherent and “threaten[s] to limit the reach of antidiscrimination law”), Benjamin Eidelson, Dimensional Disparate Treatment, 95 S. Cal. L. Rev. 785, 794 (2022) (arguing that rather than clarifying disparate treatment law, the but-for theory compounds confusion, is not justified by statutory text, and leads to “untenable results”), and Guha Krishnamurthi, Not the Standard You’re Looking For: But-For Causation in Anti-Discrimination Law, 108 Va. L. Rev. Online 1, 4, 11 (2022) (arguing “that the Court’s simple but-for causation test, by its own lights, does not advance anti-discrimination law”).Show More they have not examined how judges are applying it in new contexts. Nor have they compared the but-for rule to other formal rules on the ground. In just over three years, Bostock has been cited by almost a thousand cases.21 21.According to the Westlaw database, Bostock had been cited by 962 federal and state cases as of October 1, 2023.Show More This Article discusses more than fifty cases decided since Bostock that are related to arguably novel or potentially controversial applications of sex discrimination doctrine.22 22.This Article reviews cases through October 1, 2023.Show More It examines these decisions from the inside out,23 23.While this is a work of legal scholarship, I draw loose inspiration from anthropological methods. Cf.Annelise Riles, The Network Inside Out 6, 16, 19 (2000) (describing an ethnographic method that attempts to gain access to modern knowledge practices from within, beginning by rendering familiar and mundane artifacts visible for analysis, in contexts in which “thick description” is challenging “because the phenomena are dispersed and the cultures are many”); Annelise Riles, A New Agenda for the Cultural Study of Law: Taking on the Technicalities, 53 Buff. L. Rev. 973, 1029–30 (2005) (urging “that the cultural study of legal technology make a methodological commitment not to reduce technology to the politics, culture, history, or personalities surrounding it—that we take the agency of technological form seriously, as a subject on its own terms, as the legal engineers among us do”).Show More endeavoring to see how their reasoning works, to take it seriously, and to hypothesize about where it might go.
This analysis reveals that courts extending sex discrimination law are foregrounding formal rules as the reasons for their decisions, not sociological arguments about the nature of discrimination or feminist or other such normative theories of the harms of discrimination.24 24.Bostock itself is an example. Cary Franklin, Living Textualism, 2020 Sup. Ct. Rev. 119, 143 n.106 (pointing out that Bostock could have been justified based on “antisubordinationist and anti-stereotyping arguments,” but these arguments “necessitate more analytical work than the simple anticlassificationist argument, and conservatives generally reject them”).Show More Formal rules can sometimes circumvent roadblocks to antidiscrimination projects, such as judgments that traits that are unique to men or women cannot be the bases for discrimination,25 25.See infraSubsection II.A.2.Show More that certain groups and individuals are too blameworthy to deserve protection,26 26.See supranote 8 (quoting Bostock v. Clayton County, 140 S. Ct. 1731, 1750 (2020)).Show More or that discriminatory practices are justified by tradition or convention.27 27.See infra Subsection II.A.1.Show More The results are not always what would be expected based on crude measures of judicial ideology.28 28.See, e.g., supranote 19. I note the political affiliations of judges throughout this Article.Show More But a close look at post-Bostock cases reveals that rather than applying formal tests with the rigor of a philosopher, judges apply them with some plasticity, reaching situations that strike them as substantively unfair. Moreover, while courts extending sex discrimination law to new contexts often gesture to Bostock’s but-for inquiry, they are more likely to rely on anticlassification and similarly situated rules. A similarly situated inquiry, which asks whether people are alike in relevant respects, has been particularly prominent in transgender rights litigation.29 29.See infra Subsection II.A.1.Show More
But formalism also has well-known drawbacks. Abstract tests of discrimination suffer from the flaws of all formalistic legal reasoning: they are, to varying degrees, indeterminate, requiring that judges rely on normative and empirical premises to apply them, but deny that they are doing so,30 30.This is a standard criticism of legal formalism. See, e.g., Felix Cohen, Transcendental Nonsense and the Functional Approach, 35 Colum. L. Rev. 809, 820 (1935) (“In every field of law we should find peculiar concepts which are not defined either in terms of empirical fact or in terms of ethics but which are used to answer empirical and ethical questions alike, and thus bar the way to intelligent investigation of social fact and social policy.”).Show More and they are both over- and underinclusive.31 31.See, e.g., Duncan Kennedy, Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, 89 Harv. L. Rev. 1685, 1701 (1976) (“The more general and the more formally realizable the rule, the greater the equitable pull of extreme cases of over- or underinclusion.”); Frederick Schauer, Formalism, 97 Yale L.J. 509, 510, 535 (1988) (describing formalism as “the concept of decisionmaking according to rule,” and pointing out that “it is exactly a rule’s rigidity, even in the face of applications that would ill serve its purpose, that renders it a rule”).Show More This Article does not make any broad claims about the causal role of formal legal reasoning in judicial decision-making—causation is complex and context specific. It is also not a brief in support of discrimination formalism as a tool of progressive politics—what tools movement lawyers of any political persuasion ought to use will depend on the circumstances. Nor does it argue that sex discrimination formalism achieves rule of law aspirations such as determinacy, predictability, or judicial constraint—particularly not in legal disputes that implicate acute ideological conflicts. Rather, this Article attempts, to the extent possible, to offer a thick description32 32.See supranote 23.Show More of how thin legal rules33 33.Cf.Toni M. Massaro, Gay Rights, Thick and Thin, 49 Stan. L. Rev. 45, 46–47 (1996) (contrasting “thin” doctrinal arguments that appeal to “principles of neutrality” with “thick” arguments that ask judges to “define, or appear to endorse,” particular sexual orientations).Show More operate in a discrete set of cases. It contributes to scholarly criticism of formalism in discrimination law by arguing that, like unhappy families, each of the various formal tests is problematic in its own way. It departs from those criticisms in disputing that a wholesale move toward more substantive inquiries of the sort favored by most progressive scholars would achieve those scholars’ ultimate aspirations for the law. This Article does not endeavor to advance any one single theory of discrimination law, which is a “ramshackle institution, full of compromise and contradiction.”34 34.Robert Post, Prejudicial Appearances: The Logic of American Antidiscrimination Law, 88 Calif. L. Rev. 1, 16 (2000).Show More Rather, it adds to the evidence that a unified theory is not normatively desirable.35 35.See, e.g., Banks, supranote 6, at19 (“The effort to arrive at a unitary conception of discrimination would be misguided even if an authoritative single decision maker—say, the United States Supreme Court—propounded the definition. Any single definition would fail to account for the distinctive features of the various settings where claims of racial discrimination might arise.”); Huq, supranote 16, at 1240 (explaining that discriminatory intent is “unavoidabl[y]” “protean and plural”); George Rutherglen, Disaggregated Discrimination and the Rise of Identity Politics, 26 Wm. & Mary J. Race, Gender & Soc. Just. 391, 394–95 (2020) (arguing that the multiplicity of plausible philosophical theories of the wrong of discrimination and “discrepancies” in legal doctrines “counsel against the quest for uniformity based on the essential nature of discrimination”).Show More
Questions about the meaning of sex discrimination are timely as courts resolve issues involving the scope of LGBTQ+ rights after Bostock and the constitutionality of legal restrictions on abortion after Dobbs.36 36.Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Org., 142 S. Ct. 2228 (2022).Show More Bostock did not address whether its holding would apply to dress codes, restrooms, health care, and many other topics—controversies now being resolved by federal courts.37 37.Bostock v. Clayton County, 140 S. Ct. 1731, 1753 (2020); id.at 1778–83 (Alito, J., dissenting) (noting these among “some of the potential consequences” of Bostock).Show More While transgender litigants racked up an impressive win rate through 2021,38 38.Katie Eyer, Transgender Constitutional Law, 171 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1405, 1405, 1408 (2023) (surveying constitutional transgender rights cases from 2017–2021 and concluding that “recent transgender rights litigation has resulted in important and consistent victories for transgender constitutionalism in the lower and state courts”).Show More results since have been mixed.39 39.There have been significant recent losses. See, e.g., Williams ex rel. L.W. v. Skrmetti, No. 23-5600, 2023 WL 6321688, at *23 (6th Cir. Sept. 28, 2023) (reversing grants of preliminary injunctions against Kentucky and Tennessee laws barring gender-affirming health care for transgender minors); Eknes-Tucker v. Governor of Ala., No. 22-11707, 2023 WL 5344981, at *1 (11th Cir. Aug. 21, 2023) (vacating district court’s preliminary injunction of Alabama law prohibiting gender-affirming health care for transgender minors); Kasper ex rel. Adams v. Sch. Bd., 57 F.4th 791, 799–800 (11th Cir. 2022) (en banc) (reversing district court’s conclusions, following a bench trial, that school policy barring a transgender boy from the boys’ restroom violated the Equal Protection Clause and Title IX); Fowler v. Stitt, No. 22-cv-00115, 2023 WL 4010694, at *24 (N.D. Okla. June 8, 2023) (granting motion to dismiss challenge to state policy prohibiting transgender individuals from changing the sex designations on their birth certificates), appeal docketed, No. 23-5080 (10th Cir. July 7, 2023); Gore v. Lee, No. 19-cv-00328, 2023 WL 4141665, at *37 (M.D. Tenn. June 22, 2023) (similar), appeal docketed, No. 23-5669 (6th Cir. July 26, 2023); B.P.J. v. W. Va. State Bd. of Educ., No. 21-cv-00316, 2023 WL 111875, at *10 (S.D. W. Va. Jan. 5, 2023) (denying transgender litigant’s motion for summary judgment in case challenging law forbidding transgender girls from playing girls’ sports in school), argued, No. 23-1078 (4th Cir. Oct. 27, 2023); A.H. ex rel. D.H. v. Williamson Cnty. Bd. of Educ., 638 F. Supp. 3d 821, 837 (M.D. Tenn. Nov. 2, 2022) (denying preliminary injunction in case challenging Tennessee state law barring transgender schoolchildren from using restrooms consistent with their gender identities).Show More Most notably, a 2022 en banc decision by the Eleventh Circuit rejected a “cornucopia” of formal theories advanced by a transgender student in a case over restroom access.40 40.Adams, 57 F.4th at 846 n.13 (Jill Pryor, J., dissenting) (describing six distinct theories that the majority rejected).Show More While Dobbs addressed equal protection issues, its statements on that question are dicta.41 41.Reva B. Siegel, Serena Mayeri & Melissa Murray, Equal Protection in Dobbs and Beyond: How States Protect Life Inside and Outside of the Abortion Context, 43 Colum. J. Gender & L. 67, 68, 93 (2022) (noting that the parties had not asserted an equal protection claim in Dobbs and observing that “Justice Alito’s attempt to block an equal protection claim that was not even before the Court in Dobbs is evidence of equality’s power, not its weakness”).Show More State courts are now resolving equal protection challenges to abortion bans under their own state constitutions.42 42.SeePlanned Parenthood of the Great Nw. v. State, 522 P.3d 1132, 1198–200 (Idaho 2023) (rejecting equal protection challenges to Idaho law restricting abortion); Siegel et al., supranote 41, at 95–96 (discussing state court decisions on the right to abortion as a matter of gender equality).Show More Yet few scholars are focused “on questions of equal protection and pregnancy.”43 43.Siegel et al., supranote 41, at 73–74 (explaining that “[t]his is because, for decades, the question has been buried under the substantive due process doctrines regulating abortion . . . , and under federal statutes that prohibit pregnancy discrimination, including by government actors”).Show More
This Article proceeds in four Parts. Part I defines discrimination formalism, explains its importance, and offers a typology of formal theories of disparate treatment. Part II argues that courts are relying on formalistic tests to expand sex discrimination law in several contested contexts, including debates over discrimination based on bisexuality, nonbinary gender, menstruation, genitalia, and other aspects of reproductive biology, and sex-segregated restrooms, dress codes, and other such policies. It asks whether various formal tests have potential to further expand sex discrimination law on these issues, and explains the reasons for the appeal of formal over substantive inquiries. Part III probes the limits of sex discrimination formalism and addresses potential criticisms of formal rules. Part IV draws out lessons from this account for debates over formal equality and the future of civil rights law.
- Kenneth L. Karst, The Supreme Court, 1976 Term—Foreword: Equal Citizenship Under the Fourteenth Amendment, 91 Harv. L. Rev. 1, 39 (1977). ↑
- See, e.g., Ian Haney-López, Intentional Blindness, 87 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 1779, 1784 (2012) (“[D]iscriminatory intent doctrine excludes evidence of continued discrimination against non-Whites rooted in history, contemporary practices, and social science . . . . Meanwhile, . . . colorblindness similarly closes courthouse doors to evidence showing that state actors sometimes use race to break down inequality and to foster integration.”); Reva Siegel, Why Equal Protection No Longer Protects: The Evolving Forms of Status-Enforcing State Action, 49 Stan. L. Rev. 1111, 1113 (1997) (criticizing “[c]ontemporary equal protection law” because it “is premised on a formal and historically static conception of ‘discrimination’” focused on “classification” or “discriminatory purpose—a concept the Court has defined as tantamount to malice”). ↑
- See, e.g., Haney-López, supra note 2, at 1876 (proposing a “contextual intent” test). ↑
- See, e.g., Issa Kohler-Hausmann, Eddie Murphy and the Dangers of Counterfactual Causal Thinking About Detecting Racial Discrimination, 113 Nw. U. L. Rev. 1163, 1166, 1172 (2019) (arguing for a definition that accounts for “the system of social meanings or practices” that constitute social categories such as race and sex); Charles R. Lawrence III, The Id, the Ego, and Equal Protection: Reckoning with Unconscious Racism, 39 Stan. L. Rev. 317, 355–56 (1987) (proposing a “cultural meaning” test that “would evaluate governmental conduct to see if it conveys a symbolic message to which the culture attaches racial significance” and “considering evidence regarding the historical and social context in which the decision was made and effectuated”). ↑
- See, e.g., Richard Thompson Ford, Bias in the Air: Rethinking Employment Discrimination Law, 66 Stan. L. Rev. 1381, 1384 (2014) (“[T]he law should replace the conceptually elusive goal of eliminating discrimination with the more concrete goal of requiring employers, government officials, and other powerful actors to meet a duty of care to avoid unnecessarily perpetuating social segregation or hierarchy.”); Siegel, supra note 2, at 1146 (suggesting that equal protection doctrine might require scrutiny for “facially neutral policies” that “perpetuate, or aggravate, historic patterns of race and gender inequality”). ↑
- See, e.g., R. Richard Banks, Class and Culture: The Indeterminacy of Nondiscrimination, 5 Stan. J. C.R. & C.L. 1, 3 (2009) (“[W]e should approach race-related policy disputes in a pragmatic manner, weighing the costs and benefits of alternative proposals in each specific setting.”). ↑
- 140 S. Ct. 1731, 1737 (2020). ↑
- Id. at 1750–51 (denying the relevance of history and pointing out that “applying protective laws to groups that were politically unpopular at the time of the law’s passage—whether prisoners in the 1990s or homosexual and transgender employees in the 1960s—often may be seen as unexpected”). ↑
- Id. at 1741. ↑
- Id. The same argument works for the transgender employees—for example, a transgender woman may not be penalized for having traits that would be acceptable in an employee who was assigned female at birth. Id. ↑
- See, e.g., infra Subsection II.A.1 (discussing Grimm v. Gloucester County School Board, 972 F.3d 586, 616, 619 (4th Cir. 2020) (affirming summary judgment in favor of a transgender plaintiff on equal protection and Title IX claims), cert. denied, 141 S. Ct. 2878 (2021)). ↑
- See infra Subsection II.A.2 (discussing Flores v. Virginia Department of Corrections, No. 20-cv-00087, 2021 WL 668802, at *6 (W.D. Va. Feb. 22, 2021) (denying summary judgment in a sex discrimination case in which an employee was fired when her tampon set off a security scanner triggering the false suspicion that she was smuggling contraband)). ↑
- See, e.g., infra Subsection II.A.1 (discussing Peltier v. Charter Day School, Inc., 37 F.4th 104 (4th Cir. 2021) (en banc) (affirming grant of summary judgment to plaintiffs on § 1983 equal protection claim and reversing grant of summary judgment to school on Title IX claim challenging discriminatory dress code)). ↑
- I define discrimination formalism more precisely infra Section I.A. Cf. Morton J. Horwitz, The Transformation of American Law, 1780–1860, at 254 (1977) (discussing “legal formalism” as “an intellectual system which gave common law rules the appearance of being self-contained, apolitical, and inexorable, and which, by making ‘legal reasoning seem like mathematics,’ conveyed ‘an air . . . of . . . inevitability’ about legal decisions”). I do not suggest formal rules succeed at perfect abstraction or constraint; formalism is a matter of degree. See, e.g., Cass R. Sunstein, Must Formalism Be Defended Empirically?, 66 U. Chi. L. Rev. 636, 640 (1999) (“The real question is ‘what degree of formalism?’ rather than ‘formalist or not?’”). ↑
- See, e.g., supra notes 2, 4, 6 and accompanying text. But cf. Mary Anne Case, “The Very Stereotype the Law Condemns”: Constitutional Sex Discrimination Law as a Quest for Perfect Proxies, 85 Cornell L. Rev. 1447, 1448–52 (2000) (characterizing equal protection cases on sex as standing for the formalistic rule that, when a law, on its face, treats men and women differently, it may not be based on a generalization that would be untrue for even a single individual man or woman, and arguing that, if courts took this rule seriously, it would lead “in interesting and radical directions” like marriage equality). ↑
- See, e.g., Guy-Uriel E. Charles & Luis Fuentes-Rohwer, Pathological Racism, Chronic Racism & Targeted Universalism, 109 Calif. L. Rev. 1107, 1111 (2021) (discussing the “standard doctrinal account,” which lumps together concerns about formal equality and anticlassification in equal protection law); cf. Aziz Z. Huq, What Is Discriminatory Intent?, 103 Cornell L. Rev. 1211, 1223–24 (2018) (“Questions of how discriminatory intent is defined and proved tend to be ancillary and subordinate to a larger critique of the ideological orientation of the doctrine.”). ↑
- This is a problematic metaphor, for, among other reasons, the fact that blind people do see race. See generally Osagie Obasogie, Blinded by Sight: Seeing Race Through the Eyes of the Blind (2013). ↑
- Cf. Pers. Adm’r v. Feeney, 442 U.S. 256, 279 (1979) (“‘Discriminatory purpose’ . . . implies that the decisionmaker . . . selected or reaffirmed a particular course of action at least in part ‘because of,’ not merely ‘in spite of,’ its adverse effects upon an identifiable group.”). ↑
- Bear Creek Bible Church v. EEOC, 571 F. Supp. 3d 571, 622 (N.D. Tex. 2021) (concluding that an employer who discriminates on the basis of bisexuality is not discriminating on the basis of sex under “[t]he traditional but-for ‘favoritism’ analyses,” but is failing to act in a way that is “‘blind’ to sex”), vacated sub nom. Braidwood Mgmt., Inc. v. EEOC, 70 F.4th 914, 940 (5th Cir. 2023). Ideology is unlikely to be the explanation for this twist in reasoning. The district court judge, Reed O’Connor, was appointed by President George W. Bush, and is known for striking down the policies of the Biden and Obama administrations. Tierney Sneed, Judge Notorious for Anti-Obamacare Rulings Has Another Crack, CNN (Jan. 28, 2022, 7:56 AM), https://www.cnn.com/2022/01/28/politics/obamacare-reed-oconnor-biden-doj-health/index.html [https://perma.cc/H3G3-TMDH]. ↑
- Compare Katie Eyer, The But-For Theory of Anti-Discrimination Law, 107 Va. L. Rev. 1621, 1624–25 (2021) (applauding the but-for theory on the ground that it clarifies disparate treatment law and avoids the intent requirement), with Robin Dembroff & Issa Kohler-Hausmann, Supreme Confusion About Causality at the Supreme Court, 25 CUNY L. Rev. 57, 58 (2022) (arguing that Bostock’s but-for test is incoherent and “threaten[s] to limit the reach of antidiscrimination law”), Benjamin Eidelson, Dimensional Disparate Treatment, 95 S. Cal. L. Rev. 785, 794 (2022) (arguing that rather than clarifying disparate treatment law, the but-for theory compounds confusion, is not justified by statutory text, and leads to “untenable results”), and Guha Krishnamurthi, Not the Standard You’re Looking For: But-For Causation in Anti-Discrimination Law, 108 Va. L. Rev. Online 1, 4, 11 (2022) (arguing “that the Court’s simple but-for causation test, by its own lights, does not advance anti-discrimination law”). ↑
- According to the Westlaw database, Bostock had been cited by 962 federal and state cases as of October 1, 2023. ↑
- This Article reviews cases through October 1, 2023. ↑
- While this is a work of legal scholarship, I draw loose inspiration from anthropological methods. Cf. Annelise Riles, The Network Inside Out 6, 16, 19 (2000) (describing an ethnographic method that attempts to gain access to modern knowledge practices from within, beginning by rendering familiar and mundane artifacts visible for analysis, in contexts in which “thick description” is challenging “because the phenomena are dispersed and the cultures are many”); Annelise Riles, A New Agenda for the Cultural Study of Law: Taking on the Technicalities, 53 Buff. L. Rev. 973, 1029–30 (2005) (urging “that the cultural study of legal technology make a methodological commitment not to reduce technology to the politics, culture, history, or personalities surrounding it—that we take the agency of technological form seriously, as a subject on its own terms, as the legal engineers among us do”). ↑
- Bostock itself is an example. Cary Franklin, Living Textualism, 2020 Sup. Ct. Rev. 119, 143 n.106 (pointing out that Bostock could have been justified based on “antisubordinationist and anti-stereotyping arguments,” but these arguments “necessitate more analytical work than the simple anticlassificationist argument, and conservatives generally reject them”). ↑
- See infra Subsection II.A.2. ↑
- See supra note 8 (quoting Bostock v. Clayton County, 140 S. Ct. 1731, 1750 (2020)). ↑
- See infra Subsection II.A.1. ↑
- See, e.g., supra note 19. I note the political affiliations of judges throughout this Article. ↑
- See infra Subsection II.A.1. ↑
- This is a standard criticism of legal formalism. See, e.g., Felix Cohen, Transcendental Nonsense and the Functional Approach, 35 Colum. L. Rev. 809, 820 (1935) (“In every field of law we should find peculiar concepts which are not defined either in terms of empirical fact or in terms of ethics but which are used to answer empirical and ethical questions alike, and thus bar the way to intelligent investigation of social fact and social policy.”). ↑
- See, e.g., Duncan Kennedy, Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, 89 Harv. L. Rev. 1685, 1701 (1976) (“The more general and the more formally realizable the rule, the greater the equitable pull of extreme cases of over- or underinclusion.”); Frederick Schauer, Formalism, 97 Yale L.J. 509, 510, 535 (1988) (describing formalism as “the concept of decisionmaking according to rule,” and pointing out that “it is exactly a rule’s rigidity, even in the face of applications that would ill serve its purpose, that renders it a rule”). ↑
- See supra note 23. ↑
- Cf. Toni M. Massaro, Gay Rights, Thick and Thin, 49 Stan. L. Rev. 45, 46–47 (1996) (contrasting “thin” doctrinal arguments that appeal to “principles of neutrality” with “thick” arguments that ask judges to “define, or appear to endorse,” particular sexual orientations). ↑
- Robert Post, Prejudicial Appearances: The Logic of American Antidiscrimination Law, 88 Calif. L. Rev. 1, 16 (2000). ↑
- See, e.g., Banks, supra note 6, at 19 (“The effort to arrive at a unitary conception of discrimination would be misguided even if an authoritative single decision maker—say, the United States Supreme Court—propounded the definition. Any single definition would fail to account for the distinctive features of the various settings where claims of racial discrimination might arise.”); Huq, supra note 16, at 1240 (explaining that discriminatory intent is “unavoidabl[y]” “protean and plural”); George Rutherglen, Disaggregated Discrimination and the Rise of Identity Politics, 26 Wm. & Mary J. Race, Gender & Soc. Just. 391, 394–95 (2020) (arguing that the multiplicity of plausible philosophical theories of the wrong of discrimination and “discrepancies” in legal doctrines “counsel against the quest for uniformity based on the essential nature of discrimination”). ↑
- Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Org., 142 S. Ct. 2228 (2022). ↑
- Bostock v. Clayton County, 140 S. Ct. 1731, 1753 (2020); id. at 1778–83 (Alito, J., dissenting) (noting these among “some of the potential consequences” of Bostock). ↑
- Katie Eyer, Transgender Constitutional Law, 171 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1405, 1405, 1408 (2023) (surveying constitutional transgender rights cases from 2017–2021 and concluding that “recent transgender rights litigation has resulted in important and consistent victories for transgender constitutionalism in the lower and state courts”). ↑
- There have been significant recent losses. See, e.g., Williams ex rel. L.W. v. Skrmetti, No. 23-5600, 2023 WL 6321688, at *23 (6th Cir. Sept. 28, 2023) (reversing grants of preliminary injunctions against Kentucky and Tennessee laws barring gender-affirming health care for transgender minors); Eknes-Tucker v. Governor of Ala., No. 22-11707, 2023 WL 5344981, at *1 (11th Cir. Aug. 21, 2023) (vacating district court’s preliminary injunction of Alabama law prohibiting gender-affirming health care for transgender minors); Kasper ex rel. Adams v. Sch. Bd., 57 F.4th 791, 799–800 (11th Cir. 2022) (en banc) (reversing district court’s conclusions, following a bench trial, that school policy barring a transgender boy from the boys’ restroom violated the Equal Protection Clause and Title IX); Fowler v. Stitt, No. 22-cv-00115, 2023 WL 4010694, at *24 (N.D. Okla. June 8, 2023) (granting motion to dismiss challenge to state policy prohibiting transgender individuals from changing the sex designations on their birth certificates), appeal docketed, No. 23-5080 (10th Cir. July 7, 2023); Gore v. Lee, No. 19-cv-00328, 2023 WL 4141665, at *37 (M.D. Tenn. June 22, 2023) (similar), appeal docketed, No. 23-5669 (6th Cir. July 26, 2023); B.P.J. v. W. Va. State Bd. of Educ., No. 21-cv-00316, 2023 WL 111875, at *10 (S.D. W. Va. Jan. 5, 2023) (denying transgender litigant’s motion for summary judgment in case challenging law forbidding transgender girls from playing girls’ sports in school), argued, No. 23-1078 (4th Cir. Oct. 27, 2023); A.H. ex rel. D.H. v. Williamson Cnty. Bd. of Educ., 638 F. Supp. 3d 821, 837 (M.D. Tenn. Nov. 2, 2022) (denying preliminary injunction in case challenging Tennessee state law barring transgender schoolchildren from using restrooms consistent with their gender identities). ↑
- Adams, 57 F.4th at 846 n.13 (Jill Pryor, J., dissenting) (describing six distinct theories that the majority rejected). ↑
- Reva B. Siegel, Serena Mayeri & Melissa Murray, Equal Protection in Dobbs and Beyond: How States Protect Life Inside and Outside of the Abortion Context, 43 Colum. J. Gender & L. 67, 68, 93 (2022) (noting that the parties had not asserted an equal protection claim in Dobbs and observing that “Justice Alito’s attempt to block an equal protection claim that was not even before the Court in Dobbs is evidence of equality’s power, not its weakness”). ↑
- See Planned Parenthood of the Great Nw. v. State, 522 P.3d 1132, 1198–200 (Idaho 2023) (rejecting equal protection challenges to Idaho law restricting abortion); Siegel et al., supra note 41, at 95–96 (discussing state court decisions on the right to abortion as a matter of gender equality). ↑
-
Siegel et al., supra note 41, at 73–74 (explaining that “[t]his is because, for decades, the question has been buried under the substantive due process doctrines regulating abortion . . . , and under federal statutes that prohibit pregnancy discrimination, including by government actors”). ↑