Expedient Imprisonment: How Federal Supervised Release Sentences Violate the Constitution

[T]he Bill of Rights which we guard so jealously and the procedures it guarantees are not to be abrogated merely because a guilty man may escape prosecution or for any other expedient reason.

– Kennedy v. Mendoza-Martinez, 372 U.S. 144, 184 (1963)

Introduction

Each year, more than ten thousand people are imprisoned by federal courts without being charged with a crime, indicted by a grand jury, or found guilty beyond a reasonable doubt by a jury of their peers. Those results are authorized by federal statute, federal rule, and multiple appellate court decisions. The proffered justification: those defendants were convicted of a federal crime and, after serving their full term of imprisonment, failed to comply with a condition of their term of supervised release.

In this Essay, we argue that the federal supervised release system violates the fundamental constitutional protections guaranteed in the Fifth and Sixth Amendments. We begin with a brief history of supervised release, created in 1984 to replace federal parole. Like a defendant granted release on parole, one on supervised release is required to comply with certain conditions set by the court. Unlike parole, where a defendant could be released early from prison in exchange for a promise to abide by those conditions, supervised release does not replace time spent in prison. Best described as post-confinement surveillance, a term of supervised release can take effect only after a defendant has served the entire prison term imposed by a sentencing judge. During that term of supervised release, a defendant accused of failing to comply with any of those conditions may be arrested and sentenced to serve up to five years in federal prison—all without the constitutional protections ordinarily afforded those facing incarceration.

Following an overview of the structure of supervised release, we consider decisions of federal courts, which have repeatedly held that the protections of the Sixth Amendment do not protect defendants serving terms of supervised release and facing imprisonment. We argue that those decisions start from the wrong end of the constitutional analysis by failing to account for the role of the right to indictment enshrined in the Fifth Amendment. More specifically, a defendant accused of violating a condition of supervised release nearly always faces more than a year of imprisonment if convicted—an infamous punishment for purposes of the Fifth Amendment. As a result, we contend that the right to indictment applies to revocation proceedings, and subsequently, the Sixth Amendment rights applicable in a traditional criminal prosecution must also apply. Furthermore, we argue that there is no meaningful distinction, for Sixth Amendment purposes, between a revocation proceeding and an ordinary prosecution, and that decisions concluding otherwise rely on unsupportable legal fictions.

Ultimately, we conclude that the statutory scheme governing supervised release creates an unconstitutional workaround to the fundamental constitutional protections designed to limit the government’s power to arbitrarily imprison. Although dodging the demands of the Fifth and Sixth Amendments surely offers a more expedient route to imprisonment, prosecutors and probation officers should not have the discretion to choose a route to imprisonment that bypasses the Constitution.

I. The History

We begin with an overview of federal parole, the system supervised release was created to replace. We also touch on federal probation, a form of community supervision similar to parole, before turning to the legislative history of the Sentencing Reform Act of 1984 (“SRA”), the statute that created supervised release.1.Sentencing Reform Act of 1984, Pub. L. No. 98-473, tit. II, ch. 2, 98 Stat. 1987 (codified as amended in scattered sections of 18 and 28 U.S.C.); Fiona Doherty, Indeterminate Sentencing Returns: The Invention of Supervised Release, 88 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 958, 996–97 (2013). Professor Doherty’s seminal piece provides a thorough overview of the story of supervised release.Show More

A. Parole

Congress enacted the first parole statute in 1910, modeling the federal system after state parole systems that had been on the books in the majority of states since the late 1800s.2.Id.at 983–84.Show More That statute authorized the early release of federal prisoners who had served at least one third of the prison term imposed by the sentencing judge.3.Id.at 984.Show More The decision whether to grant or deny release on parole was committed to the discretion of a federal parole board,4.Id. at 985;see alsoPeter B. Hoffman, History of the Federal Parole System: Part 1 (1910–1972), 61 Fed. Prob. 23, 27 (1997) (explaining that parole decisions were made by the whole board).Show More and the scope of that discretion was broad: the board could grant parole to any individual who had “observed the rules of [the] institution” in which he was incarcerated so long as release was not “incompatible with the welfare of society.”5.Parole Act, ch. 387, §§ 1, 3, 36 Stat. 819 (1910), repealed by Sentencing Reform Act of 1984, § 212(a)(2).Show More Although allowed to leave prison, a parolee was still considered to be “in the legal custody and under the control of the warden of such prison from which paroled . . . until the expiration of the [prison] term or terms specified in his sentence.”6.Id.§ 3.Show More In other words, a grant of parole allowed a term of incarceration to be served in the community but did not affect the length of that sentence.

A suspected violation of any parole condition could be punished swiftly and summarily: if any member of a board had “reliable information that the offender . . . violated his parole,” the board could issue an arrest warrant and require the parolee to be returned to prison.7.Hoffman, supra note 4, at 28.Show More Only then would the parolee be afforded an opportunity to be heard before the board,8.Id.Show More which could decide either to alter parole conditions or to revoke the grant of parole entirely, sending the parolee back to prison to serve the “remainder of the sentence originally imposed.”9.Id.Show More

In the early days of the federal parole system, courts afforded only limited oversight of the board’s decisions to grant or revoke parole.10 10.E.g., Clark v. Stevens, 291 F.2d 388, 389 (6th Cir. 1961); Hiatt v. Compagna, 178 F.2d 42, 45 (5th Cir. 1949) (“A prisoner sentenced to the penitentiary is turned over by the court to the executive, namely the Attorney General, to have the sentence executed. . . . It is very evident that the whole matter of paroles is left to the informed discretion of the Board. Court action is not made a part of it.”).Show More Federal courts set forth a variety of justifications for declining to overturn the board’s decisions: some concluded that a parolee remained in the formal custody of the executive branch,11 11.Comment, The Parole System, 120 U. Pa. L. Rev. 282, 287–88 (1971); see also Anderson v. Corall, 263 U.S. 193, 196 (1923) (“While on parole the convict is bound to remain in the legal custody and under the control of the warden until the expiration of the term, less allowance, if any, for good conduct. While this is an amelioration of punishment, it is in legal effect imprisonment.”); Padilla v. Lynch, 398 F.2d 481, 482 (9th Cir. 1968) (stating that, because parole is a form of custody, a complaint alleging that the denial of parole violated the equal protection clause is insufficient).Show More while others suggested that parole was an act of grace by a “merciful executive” that could not be demanded as a matter of right.12 12.Comment, supra note 11,at 286–87; cf. Ughbanks v. Armstrong, 208 U.S. 481, 488 (1908) (describing a state’s grant of parole as “the granting of a favor to a convicted criminal confined within one of its prisons”).Show More Finally, some courts rejected constitutional challenges to the parole system by reasoning that the parole board’s relationship with a parolee was not adversarial in nature, given the “genuine identity of interest . . . in the prisoner’s desire to be released and the [b]oard’s policy to grant release as soon as possible.”13 13.Hyser v. Reed, 318 F.2d 225, 237 (D.C. Cir. 1963) (rejecting Sixth Amendment challenge to parole revocation procedures); see also Comment, supra note 11, at 288–89 (stating that the board and the parolee have a shared interest in rehabilitating the parolee).Show More Because the relationship between the parolee and the board was not adversarial, the reasoning went, there was simply no need for courts to intervene to safeguard the rights of the parolee.

In 1972, however, the Supreme Court granted certiorari in Morrissey v. Brewer to consider whether revocation of parole without a hearing violated the constitutional requirements of due process.14 14.408 U.S. 471, 472 (1972).Show More Noting that a parolee was technically still “in custody” and could therefore claim no entitlement to release on parole, lower courts had answered that question in the negative.15 15.Id. at 474–75.Show More The Supreme Court, however, disagreed. Relevant for our purposes, the Court began by explaining that because “the revocation of parole is not part of a criminal prosecution,” the “full panoply” of constitutional protections applicable in a criminal prosecution did not apply to a parole revocation proceeding.16 16.Id. at 480.Show More No real analysis was necessary to reach that conclusion: after all, parole “ar[ose] after the end of the criminal prosecution, including the imposition of sentence”17 17.Id.Show More and involved merely a decision about where the balance of that sentence would be served. Revocation of parole deprived an individual of only the “conditional liberty” granted in connection with early release from prison.18 18.Id.Show More Accordingly, it would make little sense to require the state to initiate a new prosecution simply to require the parolee to serve out the remainder of the existing sentence.19 19.Id.at 483; see alsoJacob Schuman, Supervised Release Is Not Parole, 53 Loy. L.A. L. Rev. 587, 624 (2020).Show More

Although a revocation proceeding differed, for constitutional purposes, from a new prosecution, the Court acknowledged that parole revocation nevertheless inflicted a “grievous loss.”20 20. Morrissey, 408 U.S.at 482.Show More As a result, at least some due process protections were required before parole could be revoked.21 21.Id.Show More Specifically, due process mandated:

(a) written notice of the claimed violations of parole; (b) disclosure to the parolee of evidence against him; (c) opportunity to be heard in person and to present witnesses and documentary evidence; (d) the right to confront and cross-examine adverse witnesses (unless the hearing officer specifically finds good cause for not allowing confrontation); (e) a “neutral and detached” hearing body such as a traditional parole board, members of which need not be judicial officers or lawyers; and (f) a written statement by the factfinders as to the evidence relied on and reasons for revoking parole.22 22.Id.at 489.Show More

Those requirements would eventually be incorporated into Federal Rule of Criminal Procedure 32.1, later made applicable to probation revocation and supervised release proceedings.23 23.Fed. R. Crim. P. 32.1 advisory committee’s note to 1979 and 1989 amendments.Show More

B. Probation

Federal probation has a similar origin story. Although the first federal probation statute was not formally enacted until 1925, federal judges, relying on their broad sentencing discretion, would routinely sentence a defendant to a term of imprisonment and then “suspend[]” execution of that sentence “during the good behavior of the defendant.”24 24.Ex parte United States, 242 U.S. 27, 37 (1916); see also Brent E. Newton, The Story of Federal Probation, 53 Am. Crim. L. Rev. 311, 313 (2016) (noting that federal court judges would suspend prison sentences prior to the passing of the Probation Act).Show More If a defendant failed to comply with restrictions imposed in exchange for granting her leniency in the form of probation, probation could be revoked in favor of imprisonment.25 25.Newton, supra note 24,at 312.Show More As was the case with parole, defendants were afforded little-to-no procedural protections before probation was revoked in favor of prison.

Similar to decisions considering parole revocations, federal courts routinely rejected challenges to the lack of procedural protections available before probation was revoked, on the premise that a grant of probation was a privilege or act of grace afforded by a benevolent court, or suggesting that district courts should have broad discretion over all aspects of probation in order to effectuate the “humane” purpose of probation.26 26.Fiona Doherty, Obey All Laws and Be Good: Probation and the Meaning of Recidivism, 104 Geo. L.J. 291, 330, 335 (2016).Show More

In 1973, shortly after deciding Morrissey, the Supreme Court granted certiorari in Gagnon v. Scarpelli to consider whether “a previously sentenced probationer is entitled to a hearing when his probation is revoked and, if so, whether he is entitled to be represented by appointed counsel at such a hearing.”27 27.411 U.S. 778, 779 (1973).Show More Gagnon, like Morrissey, involved a challenge to a probation revocation that had taken place without a hearing or other procedural protections.28 28.Id.at 780.Show More Citing to a 1967 decision, Mempa v. Rhay, the Court first distinguished a probation revocation hearing from a sentencing proceeding.29 29.Id.at 781.Show More Pursuant to the unique state statutory scheme at issue in Mempa, judges had the authority to defer a sentencing decision in favor of probation; however, if a defendant failed to comply with the conditions of probation, the judge was required to sentence her to the statutory maximum for the original crime of conviction.30 30.Mempa v. Rhay, 389 U.S. 128, 135 (1967).Show More Because that proceeding functioned, in essence, as a sentencing proceeding, the Mempa Court concluded that the Sixth Amendment right to counsel applied.31 31.Id.at 137.Show More

Gagnon, by contrast, involved a different type of revocation proceeding. The petitioner in Gagnon had been formally sentenced to fifteen years’ imprisonment, but the judge had then suspended the sentence in favor a seven-year term of probation.32 32.Gagnon, 411 U.S. at 779.Show More Like revocation of parole, revocation of probation under that scheme merely triggered the execution of the sentence already imposed, and the Gagnon Court therefore concluded that revocation was not a “stage of a criminal prosecution.”33 33.Id.at 782.Show More Further distinguishing the proceeding from a prosecution, the Court noted, was the absence of an adversarial relationship between the state and the defendant. In particular, the state was represented not by a prosecutor, but by a parole officer whose interests were, at least in theory, aligned with those of the probationer.34 34.Id.at 789.Show More Rather than the full panoply of rights afforded in a traditional criminal prosecution, the Court reasoned that only the limited procedural protections identified by the Morrissey Court were required before probation could be revoked.35 35.Id.at 782.Show More

In so holding, the Gagnon Court clarified that whether a revocation proceeding implicates Sixth Amendment rights or merely due process concerns turns on the nature of what the court is deciding. Like in Morrissey, the Court in Gagnon considered a term of imprisonment that had been imposed by a judge but from which the defendant had been granted a reprieve, either in the form of early release from prison or the opportunity to avoid prison altogether. Revocation of that grant of leniency resulted merely in execution of that previously-imposed sentence. Mempa, by contrast, involved something akin to an entirely new sentencing proceeding, to which the Sixth Amendment right to counsel applied.

Probation—and the constitutional mandates set forth in Gagnon—ultimately survived the sweeping changes made by the SRA. Although the SRA directed judges to treat probation as “a form of sentence with conditions rather than as a deferral of imposition or execution of a sentence,”36 36.S. Rep. No. 98-225, at 59 (1983). Arguably, then, Mempa is the only Supreme Court decision that affords constitutional guidance with regard to modern federal probation, which is a sentence in its own right and which requires a judge to engage in a full-blown sentencing proceeding when probation is “revoked.”Show More judges still had broad authority to revoke probation and resentence a defendant for up to the statutory maximum term of imprisonment for the crime of conviction if he or she failed to comply with conditions the judge had imposed in exchange for granting a reprieve from prison.37 37.United States v. Labonte, 520 U.S. 751, 769 (1997) (Breyer, J., dissenting).Show More

C. Supervised Release

By the early 1980s, the federal parole system had come under fire from both sides of the political spectrum as creating unwarranted sentencing disparities among federal offenders and sentences of indeterminate length.38 38.Doherty, supra note 1, at 995.Show More As part of an attempt to comprehensively reform federal sentencing and in response to widespread criticism of parole, the sponsors of the SRA elected to simply abolish federal parole entirely rather than attempt reforms. In lieu of parole, they created supervised release, a form of post-confinement monitoring that followed—rather than replaced—imprisonment.39 39.Sentencing Reform Act of 1984, Pub. L. No. 98-473, tit. II, ch. 2, sec. 212(a)(2), § 3583(a), 98 Stat. 1987, 1999 (codified as amended at 18 U.S.C. § 3583(a)) (“The court, in imposing a sentence to a term of imprisonment for a felony or a misdemeanor, may include as a part of the sentence a requirement that the defendant be placed on a term of supervised release after imprisonment.” (emphasis added)). Imposition of a term of supervised release was required as part of every sentence that imposed imprisonment during the mandatory Sentencing Guidelines era. Since Booker, with few exceptions, imposition of supervised release is discretionary. Nonetheless, it is imposed in the vast majority of federal sentences. SeeChristine S. Scott-Hayward, Shadow Sentencing: The Imposition of Federal Supervised Release, 18 Berkeley J. Crim. L. 180, 186 (2013).Show More As the Senate Report accompanying the SRA explained,

the court, in imposing a term of imprisonment for a felony or a misdemeanor, [may] include as part of the sentence a requirement that the defendant serve a term of supervised release after he has served the term of imprisonment. . . . The term of supervised release would be a separate part of the defendant’s sentence, rather than being the end of the term of imprisonment.40 40.S. Rep. No. 98-225, at 123 (1983) (emphasis added).Show More

As originally designed, supervised release was supposed to afford rehabilitation rather than impose punishment. The punitive portion of a sentence would have been served by the time supervised release commenced, and the primary goal of supervised release was therefore “to ease the defendant’s transition into the community after the service of a long prison term for a particularly serious offense, or to provide rehabilitation . . . .”41 41.Id. at 124.Show More Accordingly, judges were to consider “deterrence and rehabilitation,” but not the need for retribution, in determining whether to sentence a defendant to a term of supervised release and in selecting the conditions to impose.42 42.Doherty, supra note 1, at 998.Show More One important “condition,” however, was mandatory—a judge was required to order that a defendant on supervised release “not commit another Federal, State, or local crime during the term of supervision.”43 43.§ 3583(d), 98 Stat. at 1999.Show More

In line with the rehabilitative purpose of supervised release, the SRA initially provided no mechanism for a judge to “revoke” a term of supervised release. Instead, judges were to “treat a violation of the conditions of supervised release as a criminal contempt.”44 44.Doherty, supra note 1, at 999–1000.Show More In other words, anyone accused of violating a condition of supervised release would be entitled to “trial by jury (for all cases involving a sentence of more than six months), along with all the other procedural protections applicable in a criminal proceeding.”45 45.Id.at 1000.Show More

Just before the SRA went into effect, however, Congress passed the Anti-Drug Abuse Act (“ADAA”) of 1986, a tough-on-crime statute that increased the penalties for certain drug offenses.46 46.Id.Show More Most significantly, the ADAA made what was described as a “technical amendment” to the SRA, authorizing courts to “revoke” a term of supervised release and impose a new term of imprisonment, pursuant to the procedures set forth in Federal Rule of Criminal Procedure 32.1, “if it [found] by a preponderance of the evidence that the person violated a condition of supervised release.”47 47.Id. at 1001; see 18 U.S.C. § 3583(e)(3); Fed. R. Crim. P. 32.1.Show More In so doing, the ADAA jettisoned the carefully crafted procedures originally envisioned by the SRA’s drafters in favor of the revocation mechanism—and limited procedural protections—developed in the context of parole.48 48.Doherty, supra note 1,at 1002.Show More

The sparse legislative history of the revocation provision of the ADAA affords little insight into the intent of its drafters; at best, that history suggests that the amendment was not thoroughly considered.49 49.Id. at 1001.Show More The impact of that amendment, however, was dramatic; passage of the amendment restored a key aspect of the old parole system that the SRA’s drafters had worked so hard to excise from federal sentencing practice.

II. Supervised Release is Constitutionally Different

Citing principally to the similarities between the procedural protections afforded by statute for supervised release revocations and those governing parole revocations, federal courts analyzing the SRA quickly concluded that, at least for constitutional purposes, the two systems were virtually indistinguishable. More specifically, courts reflexively invoked Morrissey and Gagnon to conclude that, like revocation of parole or probation, supervised release violation proceedings were distinguishable from a criminal prosecution to which the protections of the Fifth and Sixth Amendments apply.50 50.Schuman, supra note 19, at 615–16, 615 n.200 (collecting appellate cases).Show More

To be sure, supervised release, parole, and probation share certain similarities—each involves, at one point or another, supervision by a parole or probation officer outside the walls of prison. But we argue that, for constitutional purposes, the differences between parole, probation, and supervised release are more important than their similarities. Most significantly, pursuant to the plain text of the statute governing supervised release, unlike probation or parole, supervised release can take effect only after the full term of imprisonment imposed by a judge has been served and thus cannot afford a reprieve from imprisonment. As a result, when a judge purports to “revoke” 51 51.As United States District Judge Jack Weinstein recognized, even the term “revoke” is a “misnomer” in the context of supervised release. Because supervised release does not replace imprisonment, a judge who “revokes” a term of supervised release is not taking back the freedom she previously bestowed. United States v. Trotter, 321 F. Supp. 3d 337, 346–47 (E.D.N.Y. 2018).Show More a term of supervised release in favor of imprisonment, what she is actually doing is imposing a new and additional term of imprisonment, distinct from the original term of imprisonment imposed as punishment for the underlying crime.52 52.Dissenting in United States v. Haymond, discussed further in Part III, Justice Alito posited that supervised release is equivalent to a sentence of parole:[A] defendant sentenced to x years of imprisonment followed by y years of supervised release is really sentenced to a maximum punishment of x + y years of confinement, with the proviso that any time beyond x years will be excused if the defendant abides by the terms of supervised release.139 S. Ct. 2369, 2390 (2019). But that argument ignores the plain text of the statute, which carefully distinguishes between a term of supervised release and imprisonment. It also ignores the legislative history of the SRA, which makes clear that supervised release was designed to serve a different purpose than imprisonment and was not intended to be interchangeable with imprisonment. Finally, there is no evidence that judges in practice exchange supervised release for imprisonment by imposing shorter prison sentences when they elect to include a term of supervised release as part of a sentence. Empirical evidence instead suggests that many judges routinely impose prison sentences within the range contemplated by the Sentencing Guidelines—which, of course, similarly do not anticipate that shorter prison terms should be imposed where a judge elects to impose a term of supervised release. SeeChristine S. Scott-Hayward, supra note 39, at 186 (2013); U.S. Sentencing Commission Guidelines Manual, ch. 5, introductory cmt., pt. A, sent’g tbl; pt. B, introductory cmt., § 5B1.1 cmt. background (2021).Show More

In our view, that distinction is critically important. Consider the structure of a supervised release revocation proceeding. First, a defendant is formally accused—most often by a United States Attorney or United States Probation Officer—of violating a condition of supervised release. After that formal accusation is lodged with a court, a defendant must either plead guilty to the violation conduct, or instead defend against those accusations at a formal hearing where the government attempts to prove her guilt. If the government succeeds, she faces, in some cases, up to five years in prison for each charge. Because revocation of supervised release involves (1) a formal accusation of wrongdoing, (2) followed by an adversarial proceeding to adjudicate a defendant’s guilt, and (3) leads to a new and additional term of imprisonment, we contend that those proceedings are fundamentally different than those considered by the Morrissey or Gagnon Courts. Instead, supervised release revocation proceedings are—for constitutional purposes—indistinguishable from a criminal prosecution to which the protections embodied in the Fifth and Sixth Amendments always apply.53 53.United States v. Peguero, 34 F.4th 143, 167 (2d Cir. 2022) (Underhill, J., dissenting); see also Rothgery v. Gillespie, 554 U.S. 191, 221–22 (2008) (Thomas, J., dissenting) (discussing elements of a prosecution).Show More

To the extent that courts have considered that argument, they have done so through the lens of the Sixth Amendment. On the premise that a revocation proceeding differs from a prosecution, they have concluded that the full panoply of Sixth Amendment rights does not apply. In our view, those decisions fail to account for the role of the right to indictment guaranteed by the Fifth Amendment. More specifically, in nearly all revocation proceedings, a defendant faces a potential sentence of more than a year of imprisonment if convicted—an “infamous” punishment54 54.Green v. United States, 356 U.S. 165, 183 (1958).Show More within the meaning of the Fifth Amendment. As a result, the right to indictment applies to such proceedings. And if the right to indictment applies, then a revocation proceeding—at which a defendant’s guilt or innocence is adjudicated and that may result in a term of imprisonment—necessarily amounts to a prosecution. In other words, the Sixth Amendment “prosecution” inquiry does not resolve the Fifth Amendment right to indictment issue, but the Fifth Amendment right to indictment inquiry does resolve the Sixth Amendment “prosecution” issue. Furthermore, there are no meaningful differences between “criminal prosecutions” and supervised release violation proceedings for purposes of the Sixth Amendment.

A. The Fifth Amendment

The Fifth Amendment provides that “[n]o person shall be held to answer for a capital, or otherwise infamous crime, unless on a presentment or indictment of a Grand Jury.”55 55.U.S. Const. amend. V.Show More Unlike the Sixth Amendment, which protects the “accused,”56 56.U.S. Const. amend. VI.Show More the Fifth Amendment sweeps more broadly—by its terms, it protects “a person,”57 57.U.S. Const. amend. V.Show More one who has yet to become formally ensnared in the justice system.58 58.Michael J. Zydney Mannheimer, Ripeness of Self-Incrimination Clause Disputes, 95 J. Crim. L. & Criminology 1261, 1321–22 (2005) (noting that the Fifth Amendment protections can apply before a formal prosecution has commenced).Show More Indeed, the right to indictment by a grand jury guards against “an open and public accusation of crime, and from the trouble, expense, and anxiety of a public trial, before . . . probable cause is established.”59 59.Hurtado v. California, 110 U.S. 516, 551–52 (1884) (Harlan, J., dissenting) (cleaned up) (emphasis added).Show More

Significantly, the right to indictment is triggered only when one is “held to answer” for a crime.60 60.U.S. Const. amend. V.Show More Although the historical record on the meaning of that term at the time the Bill of Rights was drafted is relatively sparse,61 61.Elizabeth T. Lear, Is Conviction Irrelevant?, 40 UCLA L. Rev. 1179, 1230 n.246 (1993); Wilkerson v. Whitley, 28 F.3d 498, 502 (5th Cir. 1994).Show More we can conclude at the very least that one is held to answer when he is required to appear and “explain and justify his conduct” in response to the levying of formal charges in a court with the power to punish him.62 62.Ex parte Wall, 107 U.S. 265, 298 (1882); see also Mahon v. Justice, 127 U.S. 700, 713 (1888) (noting that defendant was “held to answer the indictment” after formal charges were served upon him); United States v. McIntosh, 704 F.3d 894, 903–04 (11th Cir. 2013) (quoting Answer, Oxford English Dictionary, http://www.oed.com/view/Entry/8146 (last visited Dec. 21, 2012)) (observing that “answer” means “to speak in reply or opposition to a charge,” a definition recognized when the Fifth Amendment was adopted).Show More

By contrast, the definition of “infamous crime,” as the term is used in the Fifth Amendment, is well-settled. The Supreme Court has explained that infamous punishments include “sentences of imprisonment in a penitentiary and sentences to hard labor. They do not include ordinary misdemeanor sentences of no more than a year in jail.”63 63.United States v. Smith, 982 F.2d 757, 761 (2d Cir. 1992) (cleaned up) (citing, inter alia, Mackin v. United States, 117 U.S. 348 (1886)). Under federal law, persons sentenced to one year or less cannot serve their terms in a penitentiary without their consent. 18 U.S.C. § 4083.Show More Pursuant to federal statute, any sentence of more than one year may be served in a penitentiary. Thus, all federal felonies, i.e., crimes punishable by more than one year in prison, expose the defendant to time in a penitentiary and therefore trigger the right to indictment.64 64.See alsoFed. R. Crim. P. 7(a) (designating that crimes punishable by a term of imprisonment of more than one year must be charged by indictment).Show More

By its terms, therefore, the right to indictment attaches to the great majority of revocation proceedings. First, and most significantly, the statute governing supervised release revocations authorizes judges to impose between two and five years of imprisonment for violating a condition of supervised release, depending on the seriousness of the underlying crime giving rise to the term of supervised release.65 65.18 U.S.C. § 3583(e)(3) (“[A] defendant whose term is revoked under this paragraph may not be required to serve on any such revocation more than 5 years in prison if the offense that resulted in the term of supervised release is a class A felony, more than 3 years in prison if such offense is a class B felony, more than 2 years in prison if such offense is a class C or D felony, or more than one year in any other case.”).Show More In nearly every revocation proceeding, a defendant found guilty of committing the violation conduct could therefore be made to suffer an infamous punishment within the meaning of the Fifth Amendment. Further, one accused of violating a condition of release is formally charged with committing the violation conduct and must appear in court and either admit to the violation or present a defense66 66.See Fed. R. Crim. P. 32.1.Show More—in other words, “held to answer” within the meaning of the Fifth Amendment.67 67.U.S. Const. amend. V.Show More Finally, the Fifth Amendment protects a “person,” rather than an accused.68 68.Id.Show More As a result, even assuming, as some courts have done, that a revocation proceeding cannot be “deemed” a “criminal prosecution” for Sixth Amendment purposes (a proposition with which we disagree, as discussed below), the rights set forth in the Fifth Amendment apply to revocation proceedings.69 69.Indeed, courts already acknowledge that the Due Process clause enshrined in the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments applies to revocation proceedings. See, e.g., United States v. Haymond, 139 S. Ct. 2369, 2391 (2019) (Alito, J., dissenting).Show More

In contrast to the more robust dispute over whether the Sixth Amendment governs revocation proceedings, the role of the Fifth Amendment in revocation proceedings has been largely ignored. Most courts have simply proceeded from the assumption that, because a revocation proceeding is distinguishable from a prosecution, no right to indictment attaches.70 70.E.g., United States v. Peguero, 34 F.4th 143, 157–58 (2d Cir. 2022) (citing exclusively Sixth Amendment cases for the proposition that no right to indictment attaches); United States v. Cordova, 461 F.3d 1184, 1185–90 (10th Cir. 2006) (concluding that there is no Sixth [sic] Amendment right to indictment, and citing Morrissey v. Brewer,408 U.S. 471, 480 (1972)). Although some courts have held that imposing a term of supervised release to follow a prison sentence of less than a year does not transform a misdemeanor conviction into a felony conviction, that does not answer the question whether one facing more than a year of imprisonment upon revocation is entitled to be indicted. See, e.g., United States v. Celestine, 905 F.2d 59, 60–61 (5th Cir. 1990) (per curiam); United States v. Purvis, 940 F.2d 1276, 1280 (9th Cir. 1991).Show More As a general matter, we can imagine two possible reasons why the right would not apply: (1) supervised release violations are not crimes to which the right to indictment attaches; or (2) the indictment (or waiver thereof) supporting the underlying conviction for which the term of supervised release was imposed suffices to meet the Fifth Amendment indictment requirement. We consider both options below.

1. Is an Indictment Required to Charge a Supervised Release Violation?

One possible reason the right to indictment does not apply in revocation proceedings is that violating a condition of supervised release is not a “crime” within the meaning of the Fifth Amendment.71 71.U.S. Const. amend. V.Show More Although there is no clear definition of a “crime” as used in the Fifth Amendment, the Supreme Court has explained that, at the time of framing, a crime was understood to be an “act[] to which the law affixes . . . punishment” or “the wrong upon which the punishment is based.”72 72.Apprendi v. New Jersey, 530 U.S. 466, 510 (2000) (Thomas, J., concurring) (citing 1 Joel Prentiss Bishop, Commentaries on the Law of Criminal Procedure § 80, at 51, § 84, at 53 (2d ed. 1872)); see also Haymond, 139 S. Ct. at 2376 (describing the concept of a “crime” as broad and linked to punishment); Green v. United States,356 U.S. 165, 202 (1958) (Black, J., dissenting) (“How can it possibly be any more of a crime to be convicted of disobeying a statute and sent to jail for three years than to be found guilty of violating a judicial decree forbidding precisely the same conduct and imprisoned for the same term?”).Show More Of particular importance in determining whether a statute creates a “crime” is the measure and type of punishment that the legislature has elected to impose.73 73.Apprendi, 530 U.S. at 501 (Thomas, J., concurring) (observing that a crime “includes every fact that is by law a basis for imposing or increasing punishment (in contrast with a fact that mitigates punishment)”).Show More In fact, it is the nature and severity of a particular punishment that the Supreme Court has repeatedly used to delineate crimes from civil wrongs.74 74.Kennedy v. Mendoza-Martinez, 372 U.S. 144, 167 (1963); see also Hudson v. United States, 522 U.S. 93, 99 (1997) (noting that a court must utilize tools of statutory construction to determine whether a law is sufficiently punitive to transform a civil remedy into a criminal penalty).Show More

Consider that definition in the context of a revocation proceeding. To be sure, Section 3583 is not a traditional criminal statute—for example, it does not identify the elements comprising a particular offense for which punishment can or must be imposed. By its terms, however, Section 3583 does “affix[] punishment”75 75.Apprendi, 530 U.S. at 510 (Thomas, J., concurring) (cleaned up) (citing 1 Joel Prentiss Bishop, Commentaries on the Law of Criminal Procedure § 80, 51 (2d ed. 1872)).Show More to the act of violating a condition of supervised release.76 76.18 U.S.C. § 3583(e).Show More Most importantly, the nature and severity of that punishment—incarceration in a federal prison or penitentiary—is indistinguishable from the punishment imposed for committing a felony.77 77.See, e.g., Mendoza-Martinez, 372 U.S. at 167 (“[F]orfeiture of citizenship is a penalty for the act of leaving or staying outside the country to avoid the draft. This being so, the Fifth and Sixth Amendments mandate that this punishment cannot be imposed without a prior criminal trial and all its incidents, including indictment, notice, confrontation, jury trial, assistance of counsel, and compulsory process for obtaining witnesses. If the sanction these sections impose is punishment, and it plainly is, the procedural safeguards required as incidents of a criminal prosecution are lacking.”).Show More As a result, the right to indictment ought to attach.

2. Can the Indictment Supporting the Underlying Conviction Also Support a Charge of Violating Supervised Release?

A second possibility is that every person serving a term of supervised release for a felony conviction has already been indicted—or waived the right to indictment—in connection with the original prosecution. It is therefore at least theoretically possible that the indictment for that original offense could satisfy the right to indictment for any supervised release violation. After all, some courts (again relying on Morrissey) have held that any new term of imprisonment imposed following supervised release revocation is authorized by the original sentence and, by implication, the original indictment.78 78.See infra Part III.A (discussing the “original penalty” rationale). That rationale overlooks the statutes respectively authorizing a sentence of probation and a sentence of imprisonment. Compare 18 U.S.C. § 3564(e) (“A sentence of probation remains conditional and subject to revocation until its expiration or termination.” (emphasis ours)), with id. § 3582(b) (“Notwithstanding the fact that a sentence to imprisonment can subsequently be [modified due to compassionate release or corrected or appealed,] a judgment of conviction that includes such a sentence [of imprisonment] constitutes a final judgment for all other purposes.”) and id. § 3582(c) (instructing that with rare exceptions, a “court may not modify a term of imprisonment once it has been imposed”).Show More

Of course, it would be metaphysically impossible for an indictment for the underlying conviction to have actually included charges relating to yet-to-be-committed violation conduct. In addition, the idea that the original conviction somehow authorizes any new punishment imposed after revocation is foreclosed by Supreme Court precedent. Specifically, the Supreme Court has repeatedly held that an indictment must charge the elements of the crime for which an individual is ultimately prosecuted and punished. Indeed,

[t]he very purpose of the requirement that a man be indicted by grand jury is to limit his jeopardy to offenses charged by a group of his fellow citizens acting independently of either prosecuting attorney or judge. Thus the basic protection the grand jury was designed to afford is defeated by a device or method which subjects the defendant to prosecution for interference with [conduct] which the grand jury did not charge.79 79.Stirone v. United States, 361 U.S. 212, 218 (1960).Show More

Any substantive charges set forth in that indictment “may not be broadened through amendment except by the grand jury itself.”80 80.Id. at 215–16; United States v. Simmons, 11 F.4th 239, 268 (4th Cir. 2021) (“[I]ncongruity between the indictment and the conviction that a constructive amendment causes destroys the defendant’s substantial right to be tried only on charges presented in the indictment.” (cleaned up) (quoting Stirone, 361 U.S. at 217)).Show More As a result, the original indictment cannot constitutionally cover future conduct unknown to the grand jury at the time it voted to indict.81 81.Some decisions hold that, when an indictment fails to charge one of the elements of a charged offense, but there is overwhelming evidence in support of the missing element, the right to indictment is not violated. E.g., United States v. Nkansah, 699 F.3d 743, 752 (2d Cir. 2012) (citing United States v. Cotton, 535 U.S. 625, 633 (2002)). Of course, supervised release violation conduct is not an element of any offense actually charged in the underlying indictment, but instead entirely new and separate conduct that can occur years (or even decades) after the original indictment.Show More

The constitutional guarantee against double jeopardy also forecloses the argument that the original indictment somehow covers the new punishment. The Double Jeopardy Clause protects not only against multiple prosecutions for the same offense, but also “against multiple punishments for the same offense”82 82.North Carolina v. Pearce, 395 U.S. 711, 717 (1969), overruled on other grounds byAlabama v. Smith, 490 U.S. 794, 798 (1989); see also Ex parte Lange, 85 U.S. 163, 173 (1873) (“[T]he Constitution was designed as much to prevent the criminal from being twice punished for the same offence as from being twice tried for it.”).Show More unless cumulative punishments are specifically authorized by the legislature.83 83.Missouri v. Hunter, 459 U.S. 359, 368–69 (1983) (Marshall, J., dissenting) (“Where, as here, a legislature specifically authorizes cumulative punishment under two statutes . . . the prosecutor may seek and the trial court or jury may impose cumulative punishment under such statutes in a single trial.”).Show More Given that post-revocation penalties are not imposed as part of the original prosecution, any attempt to attribute those penalties to the original conviction runs afoul of the constitutional prohibition against multiple punishments for the same offense.84 84.In the Sentencing Reform Act, Congress “forbade the federal courts from ‘modify[ing] a term of imprisonment once it has been imposed.’” United States v. Jones, 980 F.3d 1098, 1103–04 (6th Cir. 2020) (quoting Sentencing Reform Act of 1984, Pub. L. No. 98–473, tit. II, ch. 2, § 212(a), 98 Stat. 1987, 1998). To avoid constitutional problems, when courts are authorized to modify sentences, they are limited to reducing sentences. See18 U.S.C. § 3582(c).Show More

In sum, the punishment imposed for violating a condition of supervised release cannot be based on the original prosecution—either the original conviction or the original sentence. As a result, courts cannot constitutionally imprison a person for violating a condition of supervised release unless she has been indicted for that conduct by a grand jury.

B. The Sixth Amendment

The Sixth Amendment proclaims that,

[i]n all criminal prosecutions, the accused shall enjoy the right to a speedy and public trial, by an impartial jury . . . [;] to be informed of the nature and cause of the accusation; to be confronted with the witnesses against him; to have compulsory process for obtaining witnesses in his favor, and to have the Assistance of Counsel for his defence.85 85.U.S. Const. amend. VI.Show More

In our view, whether or not the Sixth Amendment applies in revocation proceedings is a question with a straightforward answer—because the right to indictment must apply in revocation proceedings, revocation proceedings necessarily constitute prosecutions. The indictment, in other words, transforms a “person” into “the accused.”86 86.Although the right to a speedy trial may attach before an indictment issues, each of the rights encompassed in the Sixth Amendment attaches by the time an indictment is returned. See United States v. Black, 918 F.3d 243, 256 (2d Cir. 2019).Show More

But even putting aside the implications of the right to indictment, revocation proceedings have all the earmarks of a traditional prosecution within the meaning of the Sixth Amendment. Although historical records do not offer a precise definition of the term “prosecution” at the time the Sixth Amendment was adopted,87 87.See, e.g., Rothgery v. Gillespie County, 554 U.S. 191, 219 (2008) (Thomas, J., dissenting) (citing to 4 William Blackstone, Commentaries *289, to discern the Framers’ intent); see alsoSanjay Chhablani, Disentangling the Sixth Amendment, 11 U. Pa. J. Const. L. 487, 492 (2009) (noting the dearth of early Supreme Court opinions shedding light on the scope of Sixth Amendment protections).Show More we can glean from that record the type of proceedings to which the rights encompassed in the Sixth Amendment were designed to apply and the interests they were designed to safeguard.

First, the Sixth Amendment is distinct from the Fifth in that it protects only “the accused.”88 88.U.S. Const. amend. VI.Show More A prosecution, within the meaning of the Sixth Amendment, necessarily involves the “filing [of] formal charges in a court with jurisdiction to try and punish the defendant.”89 89.Rothgery, 554 U.S. at 223 (Thomas, J., dissenting); see alsoUnited States v. Haymond, 139 S. Ct. 2369, 2376 (2019) (plurality opinion) (describing a prosecution as “the process of exhibiting formal charges against an offender before a legal tribunal” (cleaned up) (quoting Noah Webster, An American Dictionary of the English Language (1st ed. 1828))).Show More The filing of a formal accusation transforms the proceeding into an adversarial one, with the government standing on one side of the courtroom as the accuser and the citizen standing on the other as the accused. That adversarial relationship between citizen and government is a “defining characteristic”90 90.Rothgery, 554 U.S. at 234 (Thomas, J., dissenting).Show More of a prosecution; perhaps above all else, the Sixth Amendment was designed to protect a citizen “faced with the prosecutorial forces of organized society.”91 91.Id. at 198(quoting Kirby v. Illinois, 406 U.S. 682, 689 (1972)); see also Middendorf v. Henry, 425 U.S. 25, 40 (1976) (“Yet the adversary nature of civilian criminal proceedings is one of the touchstones of the Sixth Amendment’s right to counsel.”); Williams v. Florida, 399 U.S. 78, 112 (1970) (Black, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part) (noting that the Fifth and Sixth Amendments were designed “to shield the defendant against state power”).Show More And perhaps most importantly, a prosecution is a proceeding that can result in the infliction of punishment—most significantly, the loss of liberty.92 92.Note, An Argument for Confrontation under the Federal Sentencing Guidelines, 105 Harv. L. Rev. 1880, 1889 (1992) (arguing that the Sixth Amendment was “meant to apply” when “the state decides how to punish an individual for criminal behavior”); 4 William Blackstone, Commentaries *301 (defining a prosecution in part as “the next step towards the punishment of offenders”); Search for Collocate “Punish” Within Four Words of “Prosecute”, Brigham Young University’s Corpus of Founding Era American English, Version 6.1.0, https://lawcorp​us.byu.edu/byucoeme/concordances (last visited Oct. 17, 2022) (thirteen hits) (enter query term “prosecute” in main search bar; then enter “punish” under the “collocates” tab below, with “scope left” and “scope right” set to four; then click “apply changes”).Show More

In our view, a supervised release revocation proceeding has all the “defining characteristics”93 93.Rothgery, 554 U.S. at 234 (Thomas, J., dissenting).Show More of a prosecution within the meaning of the Sixth Amendment. First, one accused of violating a condition of supervised release is formally accused of committing new, wrongful conduct in a court with the power to adjudicate guilt or innocence and impose punishment. Most significantly—and unlike the petitioners in Morrissey and Gagnon—a defendant convicted of violation conduct may be sentenced to a new and additional punishment, distinct from any punishment inflicted for the original offense. As a result, one facing revocation of supervised release is, for Sixth Amendment purposes, an “accused”94 94.U.S. Const. amend. VI.Show More—she has been formally charged with committing an act to which the law “affixes punishment” in the form of an additional prison sentence.95 95.United States v. Haymond, 139 S. Ct. 2369, 2376 (2019) (plurality opinion) (cleaned up); see also id.at 2392 (defining the accused as “an individual ‘[c]harged with a crime, by a legal process’”) (Alito, J., dissenting) (quoting Noah Webster, An American Dictionary of the English Language (1828)). Dissenting in Haymond, Justice Alito argued that one serving a term of supervised release is no longer the “accused,” but has instead been properly convicted of the underlying offense, and that any sanctions imposed for violation conduct merely sanction a breach of the court’s trust. Id.at 2392–93. As a result, he argued, the Sixth Amendment was inapplicable. Id. at 2392.But as Justice Alito also recognized, the original prosecution has ended by the time a revocation proceeding begins. Id.at 2393–95. And as discussed further below, there is no statutory support for the idea that revocation sanctions a defendant’s breach of the court’s trust. Instead, revocation can only reasonably be understood to sanction the new offense conduct—meaning one charged with a supervised release violation stands in the shoes of the “accused,” for Sixth Amendment purposes. And although the underlying criminal conviction may certainly deprive one of certain constitutional rights, the right to be indicted and the right to trial by jury for a new prosecution are not among them. Cf. Strunk v. United States, 412 U.S. 434, 437–38 (1973) (acknowledging that defendant had the right to a speedy trial irrespective of the fact that he was incarcerated in a penitentiary on an unrelated charge). As a result, the mere fact that a releasee stands convicted of the crime giving rise to the term of supervised release does not afford the government the right to deprive her of Fifth and Sixth Amendment rights in a new prosecution.Show More Finally, the proceeding convened to adjudicate her guilt—a revocation hearing—is inherently adversarial in nature. Although revocation proceedings may be initiated by a U.S. Probation Officer, a U.S. Attorney, or even the court itself, it is an Assistant U.S. Attorney, with all of the resources made available for prosecuting federal crimes, who generally takes on the burden of proving guilt by a preponderance of the evidence. And at that proceeding, the government—whether represented by a U.S. Probation Officer or a U.S. Attorney—has undoubtedly “committed itself to prosecute” such that “the adverse positions of government and defendant have solidified.”96 96.Rothgery, 554 U.S. at 233 (Thomas, J., dissenting) (quoting Kirby v. Illinois, 406 U.S. 682, 689 (1972)).Show More In other words, for Sixth Amendment purposes, the proceeding is indistinguishable from a traditional prosecution.

III. The Constitutional Work Arounds

Unlike with the right to indictment, courts have repeatedly wrestled with the question of whether the Sixth Amendment rights applicable to a traditional criminal prosecution govern supervised release revocation proceedings and have uniformly held that they do not. We consider the primary arguments advanced by those courts below.

A. Part of the Original Penalty

Shortly after enactment of the ADAA, Congress amended Section 3583 to make it more punitive. Specifically, amendments enacted in 1987 had the effect of increasing the length of the supervised release term a court could impose, and, more importantly, the length of imprisonment a defendant could serve upon revocation.97 97.Doherty, supra note 1, at 1003.Show More Amendments passed in 1994 required “revocation” and imprisonment if a court found by a preponderance of the evidence that a supervisee had violated certain “conditions” of supervised release.98 98.Id. at 1003–04.Show More

Defendants sentenced pursuant to those amendments quickly began raising ex post facto challenges, forcing appellate courts to grapple, for the first time, with what post-revocation penalties were actually punishing.99 99.Id. at 1004.Show More Relying in part on the absence of constitutional protections prescribed by Section 3583(e) before supervised release could be revoked, a majority of appellate courts concluded that post-revocation imprisonment had to be part of the original penalty for the underlying crime.100 100.Id. at 1006–07.Show More In so holding, those courts acknowledged that the alternative interpretation—that the new prison term was punishing the violation conduct itself—was constitutionally problematic. In particular, if that new prison term was punishment for the new conduct, courts were imprisoning people for conduct that often did not constitute a crime and were doing so without any of the procedural protections available in an ordinary prosecution.101 101.E.g., United States v. Beals, 87 F.3d 854, 859 (7th Cir. 1996) (concluding that revocation had to sanction the original offense because “[c]onduct that violates the terms of supervised release, like that of parole violations, is often not criminal”); United States v. Meeks, 25 F.3d 1117, 1123 (2d Cir. 1994) (relying in part on the lack of “fundamental constitutional procedural protections” in a revocation proceeding to conclude that it must be punishing the original offense).Show More

The question reached the Supreme Court in Johnson v. United States, a case involving yet another ex post facto challenge to the application of a particular amendment to Section 3583.102 102.Specifically, Johnson concerned a challenge to the application of § 3583(h), which authorized a district court to (1) revoke a term of supervised release; (2) impose a term of imprisonment; and (3) impose a new term of supervised release to follow imprisonment. 529 U.S. 694, 696 (2000).Show More Although acknowledging the “intuitive appeal” 103 103.Id. at 700.Show More of the idea that revocation sanctioned the violation conduct itself, the Johnson Court candidly explained that “construing revocation and reimprisonment as punishment for the violation of the conditions of supervised release” would essentially render the statute unconstitutional.104 104.Id.Show More More specifically, if the new term of imprisonment was sanctioning the new conduct, there were at least three major constitutional issues: (1) courts were imprisoning people for conduct that was not criminal; (2) courts were imprisoning people based on a finding by a single judge employing a preponderance of the evidence standard; and (3) where the violation conduct was criminal in its own right, courts were punishing people twice—potentially in violation of the Double Jeopardy Clause.105 105.Id. The double-jeopardy problem the Court identified in Johnson involved punishing violation conduct both as a supervised release violation and as the basis for a new prosecution. The Court did not consider the double-jeopardy problems discussed above—the fact that the imposition of an additional penalty for the original crime also violates the Double Jeopardy Clause.Show More In short, if post-revocation penalties were attributable to the new offense conduct, revocation proceedings looked uncomfortably similar to criminal prosecutions, albeit without affording defendants the requisite constitutional protections.106 106.Johnson did not make that point explicitly; it did, however, cite to Gagnon to suggest that revocation was not akin to a prosecution. Id. at 700–01.Show More Rather than address those constitutional problems, the Johnson Court offered a workaround—by calling the new prison term “part of the penalty for the initial offense,” the Court suggested those constitutional problems could simply be “avoid[ed].”107 107.Id. at 700.Show More

Ultimately, the Johnson Court also dodged the question whether the application of amendments to Section 3583 violated the Ex Post Facto Clause, rendering its discussion of the constitutionality of post-revocation penalties dicta that might reasonably have been disregarded.108 108.Id.at 713; see also Jacob Schuman, Criminal Violations, 108 Va. L. Rev. (forthcoming Dec. 2022) (manuscript at 125) (on file with authors) (noting the Court’s evasion of that constitutional obstacle and its adoption of the “original offense” doctrine could be seen as dicta).Show More Instead, and perhaps because of the dearth of other Supreme Court authority addressed to supervised release, lower courts seized upon that rationale in response to myriad challenges to the constitutionality of Section 3583. Claiming that post-revocation penalties could be “treated” or “deemed” part of the original penalty—rather than new punishment for new conduct—courts purported to distinguish revocation proceedings from prosecutions. As a result, they determined that defendants in those proceedings were not entitled to “the full panoply of rights that criminal defendants generally enjoy.”109 109.United States v. Peguero, 34 F.4th 143, 160 (2d Cir. 2022); see also United States v. Jackson, 559 F.3d 368, 371 (5th Cir. 2009) (“Post-revocation sanctions are not a separate penalty for purposes of the Double Jeopardy clause—they are part of the penalty for the original offense.”); United States v. Gavilanes-Ocaranza, 772 F.3d 624, 627 (9th Cir. 2014) (“The revocation of supervised release is not a criminal prosecution for Sixth Amendment purposes, because the violation ‘simply triggers the execution of the conditions of the original sentence.’” (quoting United States v. Paskow, 11 F.3d 873, 881 (9th Cir. 1993))); United States v. Doka, 955 F.3d 290, 294 (2d Cir. 2020) (noting defendants in supervised release proceedings are not entitled to holding the government to a burden of proof beyond a reasonable doubt or to a trial by jury).Show More

B. Conditional Liberty

The second argument invoked to reject Sixth Amendment challenges to revocation proceedings developed in response to Apprendi v. New Jersey, a Supreme Court decision issued in 2000.110 110.530 U.S. 466 (2000).Show More Apprendi considered the difference between a sentencing factor and an element of a crime for Sixth Amendment purposes and involved a state sentencing scheme that blurred the lines between the two. Building on its prior precedents, the Apprendi Court drew a bright line rule. “Other than the fact of a prior conviction,” the Court explained, “any fact that increases the penalty for a crime beyond the prescribed statutory maximum must be submitted to a jury, and proved beyond a reasonable doubt.”111 111.Id. at 490.Show More

In the wake of Apprendi and its progeny,112 112.The Supreme Court followed up Apprendiwith Blakely v. Washington, in which it clarified that “‘the statutory maximum’ for Apprendi purposes is the maximum sentence a judge may impose solely on the basis of the facts reflected in the jury verdict or admitted by the defendant.” 542 U.S. 296, 303 (2004) (emphasis omitted). Relying in part on that holding, the Court then decided United States v. Booker, in which it held that § 3553(b), which made the Guidelines mandatory and binding on district courts, was unconstitutional. 543 U.S. 220, 245 (2005).Show More defendants began to argue that, if the sanctions for violations of supervised release exceeded the statutory maximum for the underlying offense, the revocation sentence amounted to a violation of Apprendi.113 113.E.g., United States v. McIntosh, 630 F.3d 699, 702–03 (7th Cir. 2011);see also United States v. Huerta-Pimental, 445 F.3d 1220, 1222–25 (9th Cir. 2006) (holding Apprendi has no effect on the imposition of supervised release under § 3583);United States v. Work, 409 F.3d 484, 489–92 (1st Cir. 2005) (rejecting the defendant’s argument that the inclusion of a term of supervised release as a part of his original sentence exposed him to additional punishment beyond the statutory maximum).Show More Others raised more sweeping challenges to the statutory scheme, claiming that imposing a term of imprisonment based solely on a single judge’s findings—made by a preponderance of the evidence—violated the Fifth and Sixth Amendments.114 114.United States v. Cunningham, 607 F.3d 1264, 1266–67 (11th Cir. 2010); United States v. Carlton, 442 F.3d 802, 807 (2d Cir. 2006).Show More

Perhaps because the “original penalty” rationale seemed to run headlong into the holding of Apprendi and its progeny, appellate courts confronting Apprendi-based challenges to revocation fell back on Morrissey, which, of course, is a decision about parole. In particular, courts invoked Morrissey’s discussion of “conditional liberty” to justify revoking supervised release without affording a defendant’s Sixth Amendment rights. One Second Circuit case—United States v. Carlton—offers the strongest example. The petitioner in Carlton, sentenced by a district court to serve thirty-five months’ imprisonment for committing armed bank robbery while on supervised release, challenged his revocation sentence as violative of the Fifth and Sixth Amendments.115 115.442 F.3d at 807.Show More Recognizing that simply labeling that new punishment part of the original penalty did not satisfactorily resolve the Sixth Amendment problem, the Carlton court advanced a new theory. Reasoning that a defendant on supervised release—like one on parole—enjoys only a pared down version of liberty, the Carlton court explained that the petitioner was not entitled to the full complement of rights afforded one “to whom the presumption of innocence attaches.”116 116.Id. at 809.Show More In other words, by virtue of the fact that he had been convicted of a crime and sentenced to a term of supervised release, the petitioner had “surrender[ed] . . . certain constitutional rights” such as his “rights to trial by jury and to having accusations against him proved beyond a reasonable doubt.”117 117.Id. at 809–10.Show More In the wake of Carlton, other courts rejected challenges to the revocation scheme premised on Apprendi by invoking similar reasoning (and often by citing to Carlton).118 118.E.g., Cunningham, 607 F.3d at 1267–68.Show More

C. Breach of Trust

Finally, courts have deemed the Sixth Amendment inapplicable in revocation proceedings by concluding that post-revocation penalties merely sanction a defendant’s “breach of trust” rather than punish the violation conduct itself. Citing principally to the Sentencing Commission’s policy statement on supervision violations,119 119.U.S. Sent’g Guidelines Manual ch. 7, pt. A, introductory cmt. 3(b), at 498 (U.S. Sent’g Comm’n 2021).Show More courts have reasoned that any new term of imprisonment imposed punishes the defendant’s failure to comply with the judge’s order setting conditions of supervised release.120 120.E.g., United States v. Watters, 947 F.3d 493, 497–98 (8th Cir. 2020).Show More Because the punishment imposed is divorced from the new offense conduct, those courts have reasoned, the proceeding is distinguishable from a prosecution.

In United States v. Haymond, the Supreme Court’s most recent tangle with the constitutionality of Section 3583, the Court (specifically, a controlling concurrence) endorsed that rationale. Haymond concerned a challenge to the constitutionality of Section 3583(k), which provided that a judge who finds “by a preponderance of the evidence that a defendant on supervised release committed one of several enumerated offenses, including the possession of child pornography” must impose a sentence of at least five years’ imprisonment.121 121.139 S. Ct. 2369, 2374 (2019).Show More The petitioner in Haymond, who had been sentenced to serve an additional five years in prison for violating a condition of supervised release, challenged his conviction and sentence as violative of the Fifth and Sixth Amendments as interpreted in Apprendi. Noting that the petitioner had been subjected to an increased statutory maximum penalty based solely on a judge’s findings by a preponderance of the evidence, a plurality of the Supreme Court agreed.122 122.Id.Show More

Concurring solely in the judgment, Justice Breyer disagreed with the idea of “transplant[ing] the Apprendi line of cases to the supervised-release context.”123 123.Id. at 2385 (Breyer, J., concurring).Show More Nevertheless, he agreed that Section 3583(k) was unconstitutional. Unlike an ordinary revocation proceeding, which properly sanctioned “the defendant’s ‘breach of trust’—his ‘failure to follow the court-imposed conditions’ that followed his initial conviction,” Section 3583(k) was “more like punishment for a new offense, to which the jury right would typically attach.”124 124.Id. at 2386.In reaching that conclusion, Justice Breyer relied in part on a policy statement from the U.S. Sentencing Guidelines Manual. In our view, such policy statements cannot shed any light on the reach of constitutional rights.Show More In other words, the dispositive question, for constitutional purposes, was the purpose of the new term of imprisonment: punishment for a breach of trust did not implicate the Sixth Amendment, whereas punishment for new criminal conduct certainly did.125 125.Although Justice Breyer’s concurrence appears designed to affirm on the narrowest possible ground, it is arguably a broader holding—instead of merely recognizing that revocation proceedings can constitute sentencing proceedings, it recognizes that they can constitute prosecutions.Show More Following Haymond, courts of appeals rejected a number of Sixth Amendment challenges to the statute by citing to that concurrence, concluding that because revocation punished a defendant’s breach of trust—rather than the violation conduct itself—it was constitutionally sound.126 126.United States v. Peguero, 34 F.4th 143, 159 n.13 (2d Cir. 2022) (collecting cases).Show More

IV. The Constitutional Work Arounds Do Not Work

In our view, each of the primary arguments advanced to distinguish revocation proceedings from prosecutions to which the Sixth Amendment applies is without merit. Turning first to the rationale that revocation is part of the original penalty, the idea that, because “a term of supervised release is imposed as part and parcel of the original sentence,” post-revocation sanctions are “part of the penalty for the initial offense” certainly has intuitive appeal: supervised release was imposed as part of the original sentence, and the defendant was warned at sentencing of the consequences for violating the conditions set by a judge.127 127.Id. at 160–61 (quoting Johnson v. United States, 529 U.S. 694, 700–01 (2000)) (citing United States v. McNeil, 415 F.3d 273, 277 (2d Cir. 2005)).Show More

That rationale, however, ignores the plain text and legislative history of the SRA, which carefully delineates a term of supervised release from a term of imprisonment.128 128.18 U.S.C. § 3583(a).Show More As the Supreme Court has explained, “[s]upervised release fulfills rehabilitative ends, distinct from those served by incarceration,”129 129.United States v. Johnson, 529 U.S. 53, 59 (2000); see also United States v. Aldeen, 792 F.3d 247, 252 (2d Cir. 2015) (“Supervised release is not, fundamentally, part of the punishment; rather, its focus is rehabilitation.”).Show More and “prison time is ‘not interchangeable’ with supervised release.”130 130.Mont v. United States, 139 S. Ct. 1826, 1833 (2019) (quoting Johnson, 529 U.S. at 59).Show More Under Section 3583(e), supervised release and imprisonment also serve different goals; Section 3583(e) excludes the need to “provide just punishment” from the factors a judge must consider in deciding whether to impose or to “revoke” supervised release.131 131.18 U.S.C. § 3583(e)(3) (cross-referencing 18 U.S.C. § 3553(a)(2)(B)–(D)); see also Tapia v. United States, 564 U.S. 319, 326 (2011) (noting that a court imposing a term of supervised release “may not take account of retribution . . . when imposing a term of supervised release”).Show More In short, the punitive part of the sentence has been completed by the time a judge is considering revocation. Any new punishment imposed therefore cannot logically be considered part of the penalty for the original offense or even “part of the whole matrix of punishment which arises out of a defendant’s original crimes.”132 132.United States v. Flora, 810 F. Supp. 841, 842 (W.D. Ky. 1993). Further, to the extent that courts have deemed that rationale binding precedent because of Johnson, Johnson neither considered nor decided the general applicability of the Fifth and Sixth Amendments in revocation proceedings; it considered instead whether application of amendments to the SRA constituted an ex post facto violation in certain cases. Accordingly, Johnson is not controlling with respect to the applicability in revocation proceedings of the Grand Jury and Double Jeopardy Clauses of the Fifth Amendment or of Sixth Amendment rights.Show More Instead, it can only reasonably be understood as new punishment for new conduct,133 133.As some courts have pointed out, there is, of course, a statutory connection between the original sentence and the revocation term—§ 3583(e) sets a statutory maximum term of imprisonment based on the class of the original offense. E.g., United States v. Peguero, 34 F.4th 143, 161 n.14 (2d Cir. 2022). As Professor Schuman explains, however, that does not render the term of imprisonment imposed similar to parole because “parole revocation literally restored the defendant’s original prison term” whereas “revocation of supervised release results in a new prison term limited by the class of the original conviction, not the original sentence.” Schuman, supra note 108, at 172.Show More and thus violative of the Grand Jury and Double Jeopardy Clauses of the Fifth Amendment.

Similarly, the argument that revocation merely sanctions a breach of trust is unsupportable. More specifically, a judge who imposes a term of supervised release is not granting a defendant a reprieve from imprisonment in exchange for the defendant’s promise to comply with the conditions the judge sets. Instead, that judge is imposing an additional period of surveillance that begins only after the entire prison term she imposes has been served. Supervised release is therefore best understood as the opposite of trust.134 134.As Professor Schuman recognizes,[There is] one situation in which revocation of supervised release might be considered punishment for a breach of trust. If a judge sentenced a defendant to a shorter term of imprisonment in exchange for imposing a longer term of supervised release, then that substitution of supervision for imprisonment could be considered an act of trust, and violating a condition could be viewed as a breach of that trust.Schuman, supra note 108, at 174. But, as noted above, judges impose sentences of supervised release in the vast majority of cases, and, furthermore, “[n]either the supervised-release statute nor the sentencing guidelines require courts to exchange incarceration for supervision.” Id.; see also Jacob Schuman, Revocation and Retribution, 96 Wash. L. Rev. 881, 908–09 (2021) (arguing mandatory minimum terms of both imprisonment and supervision often make it impossible for judges to reduce one penalty in favor of the other).Show More As a result, any post-revocation term of imprisonment cannot logically be understood to punish anything other than the new violation conduct.135 135.Although Johnson “treat[s]” supervised release sentences as “part of the penalty for the initial offense,” 529 U.S. at 700, that treatment actually creates the double jeopardy problem of twice punishing the same offense described above.Show More

Moreover, even accepting the premise of the argument that revocation merely punishes failure to follow court orders, federal judges are not all-powerful despots with the authority to summarily imprison a person who disappoints them or breaches their trust. To be sure, judges have the statutory authority to punish persons for criminal contempt and to imprison or fine them for that contempt. But as discussed above, contempt proceedings require nearly all of the fundamental rights applicable to an ordinary prosecution. Therefore, even assuming that a post-revocation penalty merely sanctions the failure to follow a court order, the contempt authority does not justify the summary proceedings currently employed to adjudicate supervised release violations.

Finally, the argument that those on supervised release are entitled only to “conditional liberty” elides the fundamental distinctions between supervised release and parole. To be sure, the liberty of one serving a term of supervised release is “conditional” in one sense—failing to comply with conditions set by the sentencing judge may lead to imprisonment. But that is not the “conditional liberty” described by Morrissey or Gagnon. Both of those decisions considered systems in which a defendant received a benefit—freedom—in exchange for her promise to abide by certain restrictions. That grant of liberty was “conditioned” on compliance with those restrictions and could be revoked if the defendant failed to hold up her end of the agreement.136 136.See 18 U.S.C. § 3564(e) (sentence of probation is “conditional and subject to revocation”).Show More Supervised release, by contrast, involves no reprieve from prison granted in exchange for a defendant’s good behavior. In the context of supervised release, the necessary “condition” never exists. As a result, the “conditional” liberty to which a defendant is subject is distinct from the contractual-like liberty described by Morrissey and Gagnon.

Furthermore, Morrissey did not suggest that an individual on parole somehow forfeited constitutional protections by virtue of being on parole; instead, the Court reasoned that, once the government had successfully prosecuted an individual for a crime, it should not have to go through that burdensome process once again only to reimpose the same sentence a judge had previously imposed. Supervised release, by contrast, does not authorize a judge or parole board to afford a reprieve from prison in exchange for compliance with certain conditions. As a result, the “revocation” of supervised release is simply a new punishment, triggered by the commission of new wrongful conduct. To suggest that one on supervised release is entitled to lesser constitutional protections by virtue of having been convicted of the original offense, then, is to say that a criminal conviction cancels a person’s right to constitutional protections in any future prosecution. Surely, that cannot be the case.137 137.Under that rationale, a supervisee enjoys constitutional rights when indicted in state or federal court, but not when facing a significant term of incarceration for violating supervised release. The limit or grant of constitutional rights therefore would turn entirely on a prosecutor’s decision regarding how to pursue imprisonment—by going through the trouble of securing a federal indictment and formally charging a crime, or by simply asking the sentencing judge to revoke the term of supervised release.Show More

Conclusion

Those who drafted the Fifth and Sixth Amendments did so with the goal of making it difficult for the government to arbitrarily imprison a person. The current supervised release system offers prosecutors and courts what amounts to an end run around those carefully crafted protections, an expedient route to imprisonment that avoids the inconveniences of obtaining an indictment, affording the right to jury trial, and proving guilt beyond a reasonable doubt. In our view, it is that very expediency that violates the Constitution, harming not only those whose constitutional rights are denied, but also eroding—prosecution by prosecution—the constitutional structure put in place by the Framers to protect ordinary citizens from the misuse of government power.

  1. Sentencing Reform Act of 1984, Pub. L. No. 98-473, tit. II, ch. 2, 98 Stat. 1987 (codified as amended in scattered sections of 18 and 28 U.S.C.); Fiona Doherty, Indeterminate Sentencing Returns: The Invention of Supervised Release, 88 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 958, 996–97 (2013). Professor Doherty’s seminal piece provides a thorough overview of the story of supervised release.

  2. Id. at 983–84.

  3. Id. at 984.

  4. Id. at 985; see also Peter B. Hoffman, History of the Federal Parole System: Part 1 (1910–1972), 61 Fed. Prob. 23, 27 (1997) (explaining that parole decisions were made by the whole board).

  5. Parole Act, ch. 387, §§ 1, 3, 36 Stat. 819 (1910), repealed by Sentencing Reform Act of 1984, § 212(a)(2).

  6. Id. § 3.

  7. Hoffman, supra note 4, at 28.

  8. Id.

  9. Id.

  10. E.g., Clark v. Stevens, 291 F.2d 388, 389 (6th Cir. 1961); Hiatt v. Compagna, 178 F.2d 42, 45 (5th Cir. 1949) (“A prisoner sentenced to the penitentiary is turned over by the court to the executive, namely the Attorney General, to have the sentence executed. . . . It is very evident that the whole matter of paroles is left to the informed discretion of the Board. Court action is not made a part of it.”).

  11. Comment, The Parole System, 120 U. Pa. L. Rev. 282, 287–88 (1971); see also Anderson v. Corall, 263 U.S. 193, 196 (1923) (“While on parole the convict is bound to remain in the legal custody and under the control of the warden until the expiration of the term, less allowance, if any, for good conduct. While this is an amelioration of punishment, it is in legal effect imprisonment.”); Padilla v. Lynch, 398 F.2d 481, 482 (9th Cir. 1968) (stating that, because parole is a form of custody, a complaint alleging that the denial of parole violated the equal protection clause is insufficient).

  12. Comment, supra note 11, at 286–87; cf. Ughbanks v. Armstrong, 208 U.S. 481, 488 (1908) (describing a state’s grant of parole as “the granting of a favor to a convicted criminal confined within one of its prisons”).

  13. Hyser v. Reed, 318 F.2d 225, 237 (D.C. Cir. 1963) (rejecting Sixth Amendment challenge to parole revocation procedures); see also Comment, supra note 11, at 288–89 (stating that the board and the parolee have a shared interest in rehabilitating the parolee).

  14. 408 U.S. 471, 472 (1972).

  15. Id. at 474–75.

  16. Id. at 480.

  17. Id.

  18. Id.

  19. Id. at 483; see also Jacob Schuman, Supervised Release Is Not Parole, 53 Loy. L.A. L. Rev. 587, 624 (2020).

  20. Morrissey, 408 U.S. at 482.

  21. Id.

  22. Id. at 489.

  23. Fed. R. Crim. P. 32.1 advisory committee’s note to 1979 and 1989 amendments.

  24. Ex parte United States, 242 U.S. 27, 37 (1916); see also Brent E. Newton, The Story of Federal Probation, 53 Am. Crim. L. Rev. 311, 313 (2016) (noting that federal court judges would suspend prison sentences prior to the passing of the Probation Act).

  25. Newton, supra note 24, at 312.

  26. Fiona Doherty, Obey All Laws and Be Good: Probation and the Meaning of Recidivism, 104 Geo. L.J. 291, 330, 335 (2016).

  27. 411 U.S. 778, 779 (1973).

  28. Id. at 780.

  29. Id. at 781.

  30. Mempa v. Rhay, 389 U.S. 128, 135 (1967).

  31. Id. at 137.

  32. Gagnon, 411 U.S. at 779.

  33. Id. at 782.

  34. Id. at 789.

  35. Id. at 782.

  36. S. Rep. No. 98-225, at 59 (1983). Arguably, then, Mempa is the only Supreme Court decision that affords constitutional guidance with regard to modern federal probation, which is a sentence in its own right and which requires a judge to engage in a full-blown sentencing proceeding when probation is “revoked.”

  37. United States v. Labonte, 520 U.S. 751, 769 (1997) (Breyer, J., dissenting).

  38. Doherty, supra note 1, at 995.

  39. Sentencing Reform Act of 1984, Pub. L. No. 98-473, tit. II, ch. 2, sec. 212(a)(2), § 3583(a), 98 Stat. 1987, 1999 (codified as amended at 18 U.S.C. § 3583(a)) (“The court, in imposing a sentence to a term of imprisonment for a felony or a misdemeanor, may include as a part of the sentence a requirement that the defendant be placed on a term of supervised release after imprisonment.” (emphasis added)). Imposition of a term of supervised release was required as part of every sentence that imposed imprisonment during the mandatory Sentencing Guidelines era. Since Booker, with few exceptions, imposition of supervised release is discretionary. Nonetheless, it is imposed in the vast majority of federal sentences. See Christine S. Scott-Hayward, Shadow Sentencing: The Imposition of Federal Supervised Release, 18 Berkeley J. Crim. L. 180, 186 (2013).

  40. S. Rep. No. 98-225, at 123 (1983) (emphasis added).

  41. Id. at 124.

  42. Doherty, supra note 1, at 998.

  43. § 3583(d), 98 Stat. at 1999.

  44. Doherty, supra note 1, at 999–1000.

  45. Id. at 1000.

  46. Id.

  47. Id. at 1001; see 18 U.S.C. § 3583(e)(3); Fed. R. Crim. P. 32.1.

  48. Doherty, supra note 1, at 1002.

  49. Id. at 1001.

  50. Schuman, supra note 19, at 615–16, 615 n.200 (collecting appellate cases).

  51. As United States District Judge Jack Weinstein recognized, even the term “revoke” is a “misnomer” in the context of supervised release. Because supervised release does not replace imprisonment, a judge who “revokes” a term of supervised release is not taking back the freedom she previously bestowed. United States v. Trotter, 321 F. Supp. 3d 337, 346–47 (E.D.N.Y. 2018).

  52. Dissenting in United States v. Haymond, discussed further in Part III, Justice Alito posited that supervised release is equivalent to a sentence of parole:

    [A] defendant sentenced to x years of imprisonment followed by y years of supervised release is really sentenced to a maximum punishment of x + y years of confinement, with the proviso that any time beyond x years will be excused if the defendant abides by the terms of supervised release.

    139 S. Ct. 2369, 2390 (2019). But that argument ignores the plain text of the statute, which carefully distinguishes between a term of supervised release and imprisonment. It also ignores the legislative history of the SRA, which makes clear that supervised release was designed to serve a different purpose than imprisonment and was not intended to be interchangeable with imprisonment. Finally, there is no evidence that judges in practice exchange supervised release for imprisonment by imposing shorter prison sentences when they elect to include a term of supervised release as part of a sentence. Empirical evidence instead suggests that many judges routinely impose prison sentences within the range contemplated by the Sentencing Guidelines—which, of course, similarly do not anticipate that shorter prison terms should be imposed where a judge elects to impose a term of supervised release. See Christine S. Scott-Hayward, supra note 39, at 186 (2013); U.S. Sentencing Commission Guidelines Manual, ch. 5, introductory cmt., pt. A, sent’g tbl; pt. B, introductory cmt., § 5B1.1 cmt. background (2021).

  53. United States v. Peguero, 34 F.4th 143, 167 (2d Cir. 2022) (Underhill, J., dissenting); see also Rothgery v. Gillespie, 554 U.S. 191, 221–22 (2008) (Thomas, J., dissenting) (discussing elements of a prosecution).

  54. Green v. United States, 356 U.S. 165, 183 (1958).

  55. U.S. Const. amend. V.

  56. U.S. Const. amend. VI.

  57. U.S. Const. amend. V.

  58. Michael J. Zydney Mannheimer, Ripeness of Self-Incrimination Clause Disputes, 95 J. Crim. L. & Criminology 1261, 1321–22 (2005) (noting that the Fifth Amendment protections can apply before a formal prosecution has commenced).

  59. Hurtado v. California, 110 U.S. 516, 551–52 (1884) (Harlan, J., dissenting) (cleaned up) (emphasis added).

  60. U.S. Const. amend. V.

  61. Elizabeth T. Lear, Is Conviction Irrelevant?, 40 UCLA L. Rev. 1179, 1230 n.246 (1993); Wilkerson v. Whitley, 28 F.3d 498, 502 (5th Cir. 1994).

  62. Ex parte Wall, 107 U.S. 265, 298 (1882); see also Mahon v. Justice, 127 U.S. 700, 713 (1888) (noting that defendant was “held to answer the indictment” after formal charges were served upon him); United States v. McIntosh, 704 F.3d 894, 903–04 (11th Cir. 2013) (quoting Answer, Oxford English Dictionary, http://www.oed.com/view/Entry/8146 (last visited Dec. 21, 2012)) (observing that “answer” means “to speak in reply or opposition to a charge,” a definition recognized when the Fifth Amendment was adopted).

  63. United States v. Smith, 982 F.2d 757, 761 (2d Cir. 1992) (cleaned up) (citing, inter alia, Mackin v. United States, 117 U.S. 348 (1886)). Under federal law, persons sentenced to one year or less cannot serve their terms in a penitentiary without their consent. 18 U.S.C. § 4083.

  64. See also Fed. R. Crim. P. 7(a) (designating that crimes punishable by a term of imprisonment of more than one year must be charged by indictment).

  65. 18 U.S.C. § 3583(e)(3) (“[A] defendant whose term is revoked under this paragraph may not be required to serve on any such revocation more than 5 years in prison if the offense that resulted in the term of supervised release is a class A felony, more than 3 years in prison if such offense is a class B felony, more than 2 years in prison if such offense is a class C or D felony, or more than one year in any other case.”).

  66. See Fed. R. Crim. P. 32.1.

  67. U.S. Const. amend. V.

  68. Id.

  69. Indeed, courts already acknowledge that the Due Process clause enshrined in the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments applies to revocation proceedings. See, e.g., United States v. Haymond, 139 S. Ct. 2369, 2391 (2019) (Alito, J., dissenting).

  70. E.g., United States v. Peguero, 34 F.4th 143, 157–58 (2d Cir. 2022) (citing exclusively Sixth Amendment cases for the proposition that no right to indictment attaches); United States v. Cordova, 461 F.3d 1184, 1185–90 (10th Cir. 2006) (concluding that there is no Sixth [sic] Amendment right to indictment, and citing Morrissey v. Brewer, 408 U.S. 471, 480 (1972)). Although some courts have held that imposing a term of supervised release to follow a prison sentence of less than a year does not transform a misdemeanor conviction into a felony conviction, that does not answer the question whether one facing more than a year of imprisonment upon revocation is entitled to be indicted. See, e.g., United States v. Celestine, 905 F.2d 59, 60–61 (5th Cir. 1990) (per curiam); United States v. Purvis, 940 F.2d 1276, 1280 (9th Cir. 1991).

  71. U.S. Const. amend. V.

  72. Apprendi v. New Jersey, 530 U.S. 466, 510 (2000) (Thomas, J., concurring) (citing 1 Joel Prentiss Bishop, Commentaries on the Law of Criminal Procedure § 80, at 51, § 84, at 53 (2d ed. 1872)); see also Haymond, 139 S. Ct. at 2376 (describing the concept of a “crime” as broad and linked to punishment); Green v. United States, 356 U.S. 165, 202 (1958) (Black, J., dissenting) (“How can it possibly be any more of a crime to be convicted of disobeying a statute and sent to jail for three years than to be found guilty of violating a judicial decree forbidding precisely the same conduct and imprisoned for the same term?”).

  73. Apprendi, 530 U.S. at 501 (Thomas, J., concurring) (observing that a crime “includes every fact that is by law a basis for imposing or increasing punishment (in contrast with a fact that mitigates punishment)”).

  74. Kennedy v. Mendoza-Martinez, 372 U.S. 144, 167 (1963); see also Hudson v. United States, 522 U.S. 93, 99 (1997) (noting that a court must utilize tools of statutory construction to determine whether a law is sufficiently punitive to transform a civil remedy into a criminal penalty).

  75. Apprendi, 530 U.S. at 510 (Thomas, J., concurring) (cleaned up) (citing 1 Joel Prentiss Bishop, Commentaries on the Law of Criminal Procedure § 80, 51 (2d ed. 1872)).

  76. 18 U.S.C. § 3583(e).

  77. See, e.g., Mendoza-Martinez, 372 U.S. at 167 (“[F]orfeiture of citizenship is a penalty for the act of leaving or staying outside the country to avoid the draft. This being so, the Fifth and Sixth Amendments mandate that this punishment cannot be imposed without a prior criminal trial and all its incidents, including indictment, notice, confrontation, jury trial, assistance of counsel, and compulsory process for obtaining witnesses. If the sanction these sections impose is punishment, and it plainly is, the procedural safeguards required as incidents of a criminal prosecution are lacking.”).

  78. See infra Part III.A (discussing the “original penalty” rationale). That rationale overlooks the statutes respectively authorizing a sentence of probation and a sentence of imprisonment. Compare 18 U.S.C. § 3564(e) (“A sentence of probation remains conditional and subject to revocation until its expiration or termination.” (emphasis ours)), with id. § 3582(b) (“Notwithstanding the fact that a sentence to imprisonment can subsequently be [modified due to compassionate release or corrected or appealed,] a judgment of conviction that includes such a sentence [of imprisonment] constitutes a final judgment for all other purposes.”) and id. § 3582(c) (instructing that with rare exceptions, a “court may not modify a term of imprisonment once it has been imposed”).

  79. Stirone v. United States, 361 U.S. 212, 218 (1960).

  80. Id. at 215–16; United States v. Simmons, 11 F.4th 239, 268 (4th Cir. 2021) (“[I]ncongruity between the indictment and the conviction that a constructive amendment causes destroys the defendant’s substantial right to be tried only on charges presented in the indictment.” (cleaned up) (quoting Stirone, 361 U.S. at 217)).

  81. Some decisions hold that, when an indictment fails to charge one of the elements of a charged offense, but there is overwhelming evidence in support of the missing element, the right to indictment is not violated. E.g., United States v. Nkansah, 699 F.3d 743, 752 (2d Cir. 2012) (citing United States v. Cotton, 535 U.S. 625, 633 (2002)). Of course, supervised release violation conduct is not an element of any offense actually charged in the underlying indictment, but instead entirely new and separate conduct that can occur years (or even decades) after the original indictment.

  82. North Carolina v. Pearce, 395 U.S. 711, 717 (1969), overruled on other grounds by Alabama v. Smith, 490 U.S. 794, 798 (1989); see also Ex parte Lange, 85 U.S. 163, 173 (1873) (“[T]he Constitution was designed as much to prevent the criminal from being twice punished for the same offence as from being twice tried for it.”).

  83. Missouri v. Hunter, 459 U.S. 359, 368–69 (1983) (Marshall, J., dissenting) (“Where, as here, a legislature specifically authorizes cumulative punishment under two statutes . . . the prosecutor may seek and the trial court or jury may impose cumulative punishment under such statutes in a single trial.”).

  84. In the Sentencing Reform Act, Congress “forbade the federal courts from ‘modify[ing] a term of imprisonment once it has been imposed.’” United States v. Jones, 980 F.3d 1098, 1103–04 (6th Cir. 2020) (quoting Sentencing Reform Act of 1984, Pub. L. No. 98–473, tit. II, ch. 2, § 212(a), 98 Stat. 1987, 1998). To avoid constitutional problems, when courts are authorized to modify sentences, they are limited to reducing sentences. See 18 U.S.C. § 3582(c).

  85. U.S. Const. amend. VI.

  86. Although the right to a speedy trial may attach before an indictment issues, each of the rights encompassed in the Sixth Amendment attaches by the time an indictment is returned. See United States v. Black, 918 F.3d 243, 256 (2d Cir. 2019).

  87. See, e.g., Rothgery v. Gillespie County, 554 U.S. 191, 219 (2008) (Thomas, J., dissenting) (citing to 4 William Blackstone, Commentaries *289, to discern the Framers’ intent); see also Sanjay Chhablani, Disentangling the Sixth Amendment, 11 U. Pa. J. Const. L. 487, 492 (2009) (noting the dearth of early Supreme Court opinions shedding light on the scope of Sixth Amendment protections).

  88. U.S. Const. amend. VI.

  89. Rothgery, 554 U.S. at 223 (Thomas, J., dissenting); see also United States v. Haymond, 139 S. Ct. 2369, 2376 (2019) (plurality opinion) (describing a prosecution as “the process of exhibiting formal charges against an offender before a legal tribunal” (cleaned up) (quoting Noah Webster, An American Dictionary of the English Language (1st ed. 1828))).

  90. Rothgery, 554 U.S. at 234 (Thomas, J., dissenting).

  91. Id. at 198 (quoting Kirby v. Illinois, 406 U.S. 682, 689 (1972)); see also Middendorf v. Henry, 425 U.S. 25, 40 (1976) (“Yet the adversary nature of civilian criminal proceedings is one of the touchstones of the Sixth Amendment’s right to counsel.”); Williams v. Florida, 399 U.S. 78, 112 (1970) (Black, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part) (noting that the Fifth and Sixth Amendments were designed “to shield the defendant against state power”).

  92. Note, An Argument for Confrontation under the Federal Sentencing Guidelines, 105 Harv. L. Rev. 1880, 1889 (1992) (arguing that the Sixth Amendment was “meant to apply” when “the state decides how to punish an individual for criminal behavior”); 4 William Blackstone, Commentaries *301 (defining a prosecution in part as “the next step towards the punishment of offenders”); Search for Collocate “Punish” Within Four Words of “Prosecute”, Brigham Young University’s Corpus of Founding Era American English, Version 6.1.0, https://lawcorp​us.byu.edu/byucoeme/concordances (last visited Oct. 17, 2022) (thirteen hits) (enter query term “prosecute” in main search bar; then enter “punish” under the “collocates” tab below, with “scope left” and “scope right” set to four; then click “apply changes”).

  93. Rothgery, 554 U.S. at 234 (Thomas, J., dissenting).

  94. U.S. Const. amend. VI.

  95. United States v. Haymond, 139 S. Ct. 2369, 2376 (2019) (plurality opinion) (cleaned up); see also id. at 2392 (defining the accused as “an individual ‘[c]harged with a crime, by a legal process’”) (Alito, J., dissenting) (quoting Noah Webster, An American Dictionary of the English Language (1828)). Dissenting in Haymond, Justice Alito argued that one serving a term of supervised release is no longer the “accused,” but has instead been properly convicted of the underlying offense, and that any sanctions imposed for violation conduct merely sanction a breach of the court’s trust. Id. at 2392–93. As a result, he argued, the Sixth Amendment was inapplicable. Id. at 2392. But as Justice Alito also recognized, the original prosecution has ended by the time a revocation proceeding begins. Id. at 2393–95. And as discussed further below, there is no statutory support for the idea that revocation sanctions a defendant’s breach of the court’s trust. Instead, revocation can only reasonably be understood to sanction the new offense conduct—meaning one charged with a supervised release violation stands in the shoes of the “accused,” for Sixth Amendment purposes. And although the underlying criminal conviction may certainly deprive one of certain constitutional rights, the right to be indicted and the right to trial by jury for a new prosecution are not among them. Cf. Strunk v. United States, 412 U.S. 434, 437–38 (1973) (acknowledging that defendant had the right to a speedy trial irrespective of the fact that he was incarcerated in a penitentiary on an unrelated charge). As a result, the mere fact that a releasee stands convicted of the crime giving rise to the term of supervised release does not afford the government the right to deprive her of Fifth and Sixth Amendment rights in a new prosecution.

  96. Rothgery, 554 U.S. at 233 (Thomas, J., dissenting) (quoting Kirby v. Illinois, 406 U.S. 682, 689 (1972)).

  97. Doherty, supra note 1, at 1003.

  98. Id. at 1003–04.

  99. Id. at 1004.

  100. Id. at 1006–07.

  101. E.g., United States v. Beals, 87 F.3d 854, 859 (7th Cir. 1996) (concluding that revocation had to sanction the original offense because “[c]onduct that violates the terms of supervised release, like that of parole violations, is often not criminal”); United States v. Meeks, 25 F.3d 1117, 1123 (2d Cir. 1994) (relying in part on the lack of “fundamental constitutional procedural protections” in a revocation proceeding to conclude that it must be punishing the original offense).

  102. Specifically, Johnson concerned a challenge to the application of § 3583(h), which authorized a district court to (1) revoke a term of supervised release; (2) impose a term of imprisonment; and (3) impose a new term of supervised release to follow imprisonment. 529 U.S. 694, 696 (2000).

  103. Id. at 700.

  104. Id.

  105. Id. The double-jeopardy problem the Court identified in Johnson involved punishing violation conduct both as a supervised release violation and as the basis for a new prosecution. The Court did not consider the double-jeopardy problems discussed above—the fact that the imposition of an additional penalty for the original crime also violates the Double Jeopardy Clause.

  106. Johnson did not make that point explicitly; it did, however, cite to Gagnon to suggest that revocation was not akin to a prosecution. Id. at 700–01.

  107. Id. at 700.

  108. Id. at 713; see also Jacob Schuman, Criminal Violations, 108 Va. L. Rev. (forthcoming Dec. 2022) (manuscript at 125) (on file with authors) (noting the Court’s evasion of that constitutional obstacle and its adoption of the “original offense” doctrine could be seen as dicta).

  109. United States v. Peguero, 34 F.4th 143, 160 (2d Cir. 2022); see also United States v. Jackson, 559 F.3d 368, 371 (5th Cir. 2009) (“Post-revocation sanctions are not a separate penalty for purposes of the Double Jeopardy clause—they are part of the penalty for the original offense.”); United States v. Gavilanes-Ocaranza, 772 F.3d 624, 627 (9th Cir. 2014) (“The revocation of supervised release is not a criminal prosecution for Sixth Amendment purposes, because the violation ‘simply triggers the execution of the conditions of the original sentence.’” (quoting United States v. Paskow, 11 F.3d 873, 881 (9th Cir. 1993))); United States v. Doka, 955 F.3d 290, 294 (2d Cir. 2020) (noting defendants in supervised release proceedings are not entitled to holding the government to a burden of proof beyond a reasonable doubt or to a trial by jury).

  110. 530 U.S. 466 (2000).

  111. Id. at 490.

  112. The Supreme Court followed up Apprendi with Blakely v. Washington, in which it clarified that “‘the statutory maximum’ for Apprendi purposes is the maximum sentence a judge may impose solely on the basis of the facts reflected in the jury verdict or admitted by the defendant.” 542 U.S. 296, 303 (2004) (emphasis omitted). Relying in part on that holding, the Court then decided United States v. Booker, in which it held that § 3553(b), which made the Guidelines mandatory and binding on district courts, was unconstitutional. 543 U.S. 220, 245 (2005).

  113. E.g., United States v. McIntosh, 630 F.3d 699, 702–03 (7th Cir. 2011); see also United States v. Huerta-Pimental, 445 F.3d 1220, 1222–25 (9th Cir. 2006) (holding Apprendi has no effect on the imposition of supervised release under § 3583); United States v. Work, 409 F.3d 484, 489–92 (1st Cir. 2005) (rejecting the defendant’s argument that the inclusion of a term of supervised release as a part of his original sentence exposed him to additional punishment beyond the statutory maximum).

  114. United States v. Cunningham, 607 F.3d 1264, 1266–67 (11th Cir. 2010); United States v. Carlton, 442 F.3d 802, 807 (2d Cir. 2006).

  115. 442 F.3d at 807.

  116. Id. at 809.

  117. Id. at 809–10.

  118. E.g., Cunningham, 607 F.3d at 1267–68.

  119. U.S. Sent’g Guidelines Manual ch. 7, pt. A, introductory cmt. 3(b), at 498 (U.S. Sent’g Comm’n 2021).

  120. E.g., United States v. Watters, 947 F.3d 493, 497–98 (8th Cir. 2020).

  121. 139 S. Ct. 2369, 2374 (2019).

  122. Id.

  123. Id. at 2385 (Breyer, J., concurring).

  124. Id. at 2386. In reaching that conclusion, Justice Breyer relied in part on a policy statement from the U.S. Sentencing Guidelines Manual. In our view, such policy statements cannot shed any light on the reach of constitutional rights.

  125. Although Justice Breyer’s concurrence appears designed to affirm on the narrowest possible ground, it is arguably a broader holding—instead of merely recognizing that revocation proceedings can constitute sentencing proceedings, it recognizes that they can constitute prosecutions.

  126. United States v. Peguero, 34 F.4th 143, 159 n.13 (2d Cir. 2022) (collecting cases).

  127. Id. at 160–61 (quoting Johnson v. United States, 529 U.S. 694, 700–01 (2000)) (citing United States v. McNeil, 415 F.3d 273, 277 (2d Cir. 2005)).

  128. 18 U.S.C. § 3583(a).

  129. United States v. Johnson, 529 U.S. 53, 59 (2000); see also United States v. Aldeen, 792 F.3d 247, 252 (2d Cir. 2015) (“Supervised release is not, fundamentally, part of the punishment; rather, its focus is rehabilitation.”).

  130. Mont v. United States, 139 S. Ct. 1826, 1833 (2019) (quoting Johnson, 529 U.S. at 59).

  131. 18 U.S.C. § 3583(e)(3) (cross-referencing 18 U.S.C. § 3553(a)(2)(B)–(D)); see also Tapia v. United States, 564 U.S. 319, 326 (2011) (noting that a court imposing a term of supervised release “may not take account of retribution . . . when imposing a term of supervised release”).

  132. United States v. Flora, 810 F. Supp. 841, 842 (W.D. Ky. 1993). Further, to the extent that courts have deemed that rationale binding precedent because of Johnson, Johnson neither considered nor decided the general applicability of the Fifth and Sixth Amendments in revocation proceedings; it considered instead whether application of amendments to the SRA constituted an ex post facto violation in certain cases. Accordingly, Johnson is not controlling with respect to the applicability in revocation proceedings of the Grand Jury and Double Jeopardy Clauses of the Fifth Amendment or of Sixth Amendment rights.

  133. As some courts have pointed out, there is, of course, a statutory connection between the original sentence and the revocation term—§ 3583(e) sets a statutory maximum term of imprisonment based on the class of the original offense. E.g., United States v. Peguero, 34 F.4th 143, 161 n.14 (2d Cir. 2022). As Professor Schuman explains, however, that does not render the term of imprisonment imposed similar to parole because “parole revocation literally restored the defendant’s original prison term” whereas “revocation of supervised release results in a new prison term limited by the class of the original conviction, not the original sentence.” Schuman, supra note 108, at 172.

  134. As Professor Schuman recognizes,

    [There is] one situation in which revocation of supervised release might be considered punishment for a breach of trust. If a judge sentenced a defendant to a shorter term of imprisonment in exchange for imposing a longer term of supervised release, then that substitution of supervision for imprisonment could be considered an act of trust, and violating a condition could be viewed as a breach of that trust.

    Schuman, supra note 108, at 174. But, as noted above, judges impose sentences of supervised release in the vast majority of cases, and, furthermore, “[n]either the supervised-release statute nor the sentencing guidelines require courts to exchange incarceration for supervision.” Id.; see also Jacob Schuman, Revocation and Retribution, 96 Wash. L. Rev. 881, 908–09 (2021) (arguing mandatory minimum terms of both imprisonment and supervision often make it impossible for judges to reduce one penalty in favor of the other).

  135. Although Johnson “treat[s]” supervised release sentences as “part of the penalty for the initial offense,” 529 U.S. at 700, that treatment actually creates the double jeopardy problem of twice punishing the same offense described above.

  136. See 18 U.S.C. § 3564(e) (sentence of probation is “conditional and subject to revocation”).

  137. Under that rationale, a supervisee enjoys constitutional rights when indicted in state or federal court, but not when facing a significant term of incarceration for violating supervised release. The limit or grant of constitutional rights therefore would turn entirely on a prosecutor’s decision regarding how to pursue imprisonment—by going through the trouble of securing a federal indictment and formally charging a crime, or by simply asking the sentencing judge to revoke the term of supervised release.

On Rawlsian Contractualism and the Private Law

Forthcoming in Print, November 2022.

Introduction: Paradigm Shift and the Rejection of the Conventional View

Shifts in academic paradigms are rare. Still, it was not long ago that the values taken to govern the private law were thought to be distinct from the values governing taxation and transfer. This was thought to be true, although for different reasons, in both philosophical and economic accounts of private law. The question was, for example, whether the law of contract and tort is properly governed by the values of autonomy and corrective justice or by distributive concerns instead. The conventional, indeed, the nearly universal view of Rawlsianism—the overwhelmingly dominant theory of liberalism and distributive justice—was that the private law lies beyond the scope of Rawls’s two principles of justice.1.See, e.g., Bruce A. Ackerman, Social Justice in the Liberal State 195 (1980); David Lyons, Ethics and the Rule of Law 131–32 (1984) (asserting “the principles of justice” “do not apply to private arrangements and transactions”); Anthony T. Kronman, Contract Law and Distributive Justice, 89 Yale L.J. 472, 474, 477 (1980) (noting the “unconcern with the distributive consequences of . . . private arrangements”).Show More

Simply put, for Rawlsianism, the private law was not thought to be the province of distributive concerns. In more academic terms, the private law is not properly understood to be subject to Rawls’s range-limited principles of justice. In this conventional view, the private law is not part of what Rawls describes as “the basic structure of society,” which is roughly limited to basic constitutional liberties and taxation and transfer. This view invites the conclusion that Rawlsian political philosophy—despite its lexically ordered, distributive demand that economic institutions are to be arranged to the maximal benefit of the least well-off—is stunningly neutral with respect to the economic arrangements and ordering of the private law. This thinking led to the conclusion that the private law, if it is to exist, may be justified by values or principles other than Rawls’s lexically ordered principles of justice, whether wealth-maximization, autonomy, or pre-conceived or even pre-political notions of property entitlement.2.Kevin A. Kordana & David H. Tabachnick, Rawls and Contract Law, 73 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 598, 599–600 (2005) [hereinafter Kordana & Tabachnick, Rawls & Contract].Show More

At the same time, the dominant view in law and economics has been that the private law should be sanitized of egalitarian or equity-oriented values.3.Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell, Why the Legal System Is Less Efficient than the Income Tax in Redistributing Income, 23 J. Legal Stud. 667, 667–69 (1994).Show More The seductive idea was that any desired egalitarian moves could be achieved more efficiently through systems of income taxation and transfer than through any egalitarian alterations in private law rules. The conclusion was that the private law should be constructed to maximize wealth (e.g., optimal deterrence in tort), leaving equity-oriented demands for the system of income taxation and transfer.4.Id.Show More The argument’s invited conclusion was that any egalitarian (i.e., non-wealth-maximizing) adjustments to private law rules are inefficient, even if well-intentioned, private law constructions. If one conjoins the conclusions of both arguments, even a Rawlsian arguably ought to adopt the wealth maximizing conception of the private law.

Our early work, arguing against the conventional view, lead to a sustained analysis of this law and economics argument as well.5.David Blankfein-Tabachnick & Kevin A. Kordana, Kaplow and Shavell and the Priority of Income Taxation and Transfer, 69 Hastings L.J. 1 (2017). In outlining what he terms the three most crucial scholarly “caveats” to Kaplow and Shavell’s argument, Guttentag writes,A second caveat to the double-distortion presumption has to do with property rights. . . . Blankfein-Tabachnick and Kordana argue that taking property rights as a given is deeply problematic for the double-distortion presumption because property rights themselves are a creation of the legal system. Moreover, property rights have significant effects on the distribution of income and wealth.Michael D. Guttentag, Law, Taxes, Inequality, and Surplus, 102 B.U. L. Rev. 1329, 1336–37 (2022).Show More We have argued that there is an “entitlement” flaw in both conventional approaches.6.Blankfein-Tabachnick & Kordana, supra note 5, at 8; Kevin A. Kordana & David H. Tabachnick, Taxation, the Private Law, and Distributive Justice, 23 Soc. Phil. & Pol’y 142, 163 (2006) (“Kaplow and Shavell appear to assume the existence of an underlying system of propertyownership and free markets. [The] issue, however, is the very question of the form that property rules should take; that is, we are interested in the question of whether the equity-oriented values that differing theorists hold are best met through tax and transfer, or through (in part) the rules of property law. Thus, it is not clear that Kaplow and Shavell’s discussion, which compares tax and transfer to a tort rule (in isolation) and concludes that tax and transfer is superior in terms of economic efficiency, would (also) apply to the question of the underlying set of property rules.”).Show More Despite well-entrenched views on both sides, our objection has been well-received,7.Kordana & Tabachnick, Rawls & Contract, supra note 2, at 632 (“Our conclusions are bold. . . . [C]ontrary to the conventionally held narrow conception, contract law is within the basic structure . . . [and] the door is open for a deeper understanding of the role that private law plays in Rawlsian political philosophy—it is no longer accurate to believe that Rawlsianism is silent on matters of contract and private ordering . . . .”). Shapiro, for example, notes the similarity between our position in Kordana & Tabachnick, Rawls & Contract, supra note 2, and the recent scholarship, aptly drawing conclusions from the perspective of the new paradigm, taking its baseline as given. Matthew A. Shapiro, Distributing Civil Justice, 109 Geo. L.J. 1473, 1531 (2021). “Rawls’s theory thus does not defuse the conflicts between distributive justice and the liberal state’s other roles so much as deny them, by assigning distributive justice effective, if not formal, priority over other imperatives.” Id. at 1532. He then contrasts the new baseline with that of the former “conventional” view, ably recognizing the conflict within that view, and holding that it is “[o]nly by diluting the requirements of distributive justice” that one might “manage to harmonize them with [backward-looking or deontic] dispute resolution and rights enforcement.” Id. at 1533.Show More and change is upon the legal academy. A wide range of scholars have begun to reject these two conventional views.8.See, e.g., Samuel Scheffler, Distributive Justice, the Basic Structure and the Place of Private Law, H.L.A. Hart Memorial Lecture (May 2014), in 35 Oxford J. Legal Stud. 213, 233 (2015); Samuel Freeman, Liberalism and Distributive Justice 168, 192–93 (2018) (arguing Rawls’s principles apply to the private law); Richard L. Revesz, Regulation and Distribution, 93 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 1489, 1518 (2018) (asserting distributional concerns, not just wealth maximization, should play a broader role in regulation).Show More But in our view, scholars have not always fully recognized what we take to be the full ramifications of the private law being constructed by distributive principles.9.E.g., Arthur Ripstein, Private Wrongs 291 (2016); Freeman, supra note 8, at 185; Zachary Liscow, Note, Reducing Inequality on the Cheap: When Legal Rule Design Should Incorporate Equity as Well as Efficiency, 123 Yale L.J. 2478, 2486–87 (2014).Show More

As we say, academic paradigm shifts are rare; being at the center of one is rarer still. We are honored that the Virginia Law Review has provided us an opportunity to continue the dialogue that proceeds at the heights of the legal academy. In what follows, we aim to discuss our position regarding Rawlsian private law while engaging with scholars who have further developed this complex debate. Ultimately, we hold that, despite the purported complications, there is, as we path-breakingly argue, a Rawlsian account of the private law.

For Rawls, the “basic structure” of society is understood to embody political and legal institutions that materially affect citizens’ life prospects, such as basic constitutional liberties, security of the person, the system of taxation and transfer, schooling, and fiscal policy. These institutions are taken to be subject to and governed by what Rawls famously calls “the two principles of justice.”10 10.John Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement 42–43 (2001) [hereinafter Rawls, JaF] (“The two principles of justice [state] (a) Each person has the same indefeasible claim to a fully adequate scheme of equal basic liberties . . . and (b) Social and economic inequalities are to satisfy two conditions: first, they are to be attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair equality of opportunity; and second, they are to be to the greatest benefit of the least-advantaged members of society (the difference principle).”).Show More However, significant scholarly controversy has arisen over the question of whether the private law (e.g., contract, tort, property, etc.) is properly understood to be within the basic structure of society.11 11.As we noted supra note 1, Bruce Ackerman, David Lyons, and Anthony Kronman held the conventional or narrow view that private law lies outside the basic structure. But cf. Kronman, supra note 1, at 475 (suggesting that Rawls should not have narrowed). Scheffler posits that Ripstein views private law as lying within the basic structure, Scheffler, supra note 8, at 232 (“Suppose we accept that, although private law is part of the basic structure, there is nevertheless room for it to enjoy the limited independence from distributive principles that Ripstein envisions.”), but this view is contested. See Kevin A. Kordana & David H. Tabachnick, On Belling the Cat: Rawls and Tort as Corrective Justice, 92 Va. L. Rev. 1279, 1291–92 (2006) [hereinafter Kordana & Tabachnick, Belling the Cat] (interpreting Ripstein as holding the narrow view); Freeman, supra note 8, at 168 (“[For] Ripstein . . . private law ‘has a certain kind of independence’ and should lie outside the basic structure . . . ”). In his newer work, Ripstein side-steps the question. Ripstein, supra note 9, at 291 (“The specifics of Rawls’s formulation need not concern us . . . .”). Murphy holds that the private law is inside the basic structure and that any attempt at narrowing in Rawls’s The Basic Structure as Subject is predicated on a textual mistake. Liam Murphy, Institutions and the Demands of Justice, 27 Phil. & Pub. Affs. 251, 261 & n.30 (1999); Liam Murphy, The Artificial Morality of Private Law: The Persistence of An Illusion, 70 U. Toronto L.J. 453, 457 n.11 (2020) [hereinafter Murphy, Artificial Morality] (“Rawls himself proposed evaluating institutions such as property and contract solely on the basis of social justice as identified by his two principles, which do not obviously have room for values distinctively associated with private ordering.”). Freeman and Scheffler agree that the private law is part of the basic structure. See Scheffler, supra note 8; Freeman, supra note 8; see also Aditi Bagchi, Distributive Injustice and Private Law, 60 Hastings L.J. 105, 109–11 (2008) (discussing the role of distributive justice in contract law).Show More

The controversy over the question of the breadth of the basic structure is understandable: Rawls is believed to have been less than perfectly consistent. But, with regard to the specific relationship between the private law and the basic structure, we have argued that the historically conventional view—that private law is beyond the reach of the two principles of justice—must be mistaken.

It is important to understand what is at issue in this debate. It is neither a mere scholastic exercise, nor a simple game of words; significant matters of social and economic justice are at stake. Consider, for example, the so-called “causal” requirement in tort law—typically associated with the corrective justice conception. The idea here is that, from the perspective of a consequentialist approach, tort liability ought to be constrained: tort defendants are taken to be liable only for harm they have “caused” plaintiffs and they owe a duty of repair only to such plaintiffs. This “bilateral” or interpersonal relationship, although stated several ways, is central, for example, to backward-looking approaches to tort, even despite the contested status of the concept of causation.12 12.H.L.A. Hart & A.M. Honoré, Causation in the Law 58 (1959).Show More

While the causal requirement may be a necessary condition to a number of conceptions of justice, it can also serve as a significant impediment to otherwise seemingly just “systems” or distributive approaches to accident management.13 13.Guido Calabresi, Toward A Unified Theory of Torts, 1 J. Tort L. 1, 1 (2007) (“Yes, all that can go out of torts . . .”—referring to causation and the other “hornbook [elements] of liability”—“but tort law won’t cease being.”).Show More Consider for example, unjustified risk-taking,14 14.George P. Fletcher, Fairness and Utility in Tort Theory, 85 Harv. L. Rev. 537, 540–43 (1972).Show More whether reckless or negligent. Such activity, absent an actualized harm, is insufficient to incurring tortious liability. So, ex ante accident management systems that focus on liability for unjustified risk imposition are objectionable for failing to satisfy the causal requirement. Still, ex ante liability, properly and narrowly assigned, is an important tool in the social planning and institutional design of accident management. It is useful, for example, in cost spreading and deterrence,15 15.Guido Calabresi, The Costs of Accidents: A Legal and Economic Analysis 70 (1970).Show More both of which can be instrumental to achieving certain accounts of social justice.16 16.John Rawls, A Theory of Justice 212–13 (2d ed. 1999) [hereinafter Rawls, TJ] (considering the possibility of strict liability).Show More

Indeed, our own legal system regulates driving a motor vehicle not only with tort, but also with criminal law. The latter imposes liability for what might be termed risk imposition even in the absence of harm caused—for example, penalties for speeding, driving under the influence, and violating various other traffic laws. If tort law were to be subject to the goals of social planning and distributive justice, say, a special concern for the least well-off or people most likely to bear the cost of accidents, swaths of the causal requirement may need to be jettisoned. In addition to the traffic example, market share liability, where liability is predicated upon plaintiffs’ share of a market in faulty products, as opposed to causation, also might be a common approach to tort liability and accident management. While the imposition of liability in these instances fails to comport with the traditionalist causal requirement, it may be crucial to certain forms of accident management, whether conducive to advancing the position of the poor or creating optimal deterrence with the aim of wealth creation.17 17.See, e.g., Richard A. Posner, Economic Analysis of Law 241–45 (9th ed. 2014); A. Mitchell Polinsky & Steven Shavell, Punitive Damages: An Economic Analysis, 111 Harv. L. Rev. 869, 918–20 (1999) (noting defendants should face liability above the harm caused when their gain is socially illicit).Show More

I. Distributivism and the Private Law

A. New Perspectives

The recent and overwhelming trend in the literature has been to concede, as we have long argued, that the private law, properly understood, is part of the basic structure. Yet important scholars seemingly hold that this dramatic change may not have the full implications for the private law’s substantive construction that one might expect. This is puzzling, given the Rawlsian stipulation that the basic structure defines the range-limitation of the two principles of justice.18 18.Rawls, JaF, supra note 10, at 12.Show More Indeed, one begins to wonder what the substantive difference is between a set of institutions being inside versus outside the basic structure, were the former not to entail them being subject to (i.e., governed by) the two principles of justice. The ultimate question is whether the two principles of justice would construct a substantive private law. Conceiving of the private law as inside the basic structure but not subject to the two principles of justice seems paradoxical. But scholars have worked to address the paradox. That is, they aim to construct strategies that purport to demonstrate the compatibility between Rawlsian distributive principles and values drawn from alternative accounts of the private law.

B. Conceptions of Distributivism

In the H.L.A. Hart Memorial Lecture, Samuel Scheffler, in a dramatic departure from the conventional view, has argued that the private law, for Rawls, must be located within the basic structure.19 19.Scheffler, supra note 8.Show More He starts by rejecting the view that the private law might lie outside the basic structure,20 20.Id. at 217–22.Show More notably describing the historically conventional view as intellectually “feeble,” and asks what this conception entails for the private law’s substantive construction.21 21.Id. at 233–34.Show More Scheffler discusses several well-known possibilities. The first he terms “strong distributivism,” which provides that the private law “should be designed solely to serve the distributive purposes of the difference principle.”22 22.Id. at 222.Show More He correctly rejects this position, as we have, as it ignores the lexical priority of the first (liberty-oriented) principle of justice and equality of opportunity.23 23.Id.; Kordana & Tabachnick, Rawls & Contract, supra note 2, at 610 (rejecting the strong distributivism position); Kordana & Tabachnick, Belling the Cat, supra note 11, at 1293 (same).Show More Scheffler’s “strong distributivism” focuses exclusively upon economic distribution, the domain of the difference principle (requiring distributive shares to maximize the position of the least well-off). The Rawlsian position, however, is that the liberty and opportunity principles, taken in lexical priority, constrain the difference principle’s economic construction. The first principle of justice, for example, might play a significant role in providing for the security of the person in the construction of an accident reduction and compensation scheme. Presumably, however, the difference principle would nonetheless construct much of the private law, since a great deal of the private law is chiefly concerned with economic matters. This is what we have called the High Rawlsian position.24 24.Kordana & Tabachnick, Rawls & Contract, supra note 2, at 609.Show More Importantly, the first principle of justice is not robust in the construction of property, economic relations, or the structure of the market. It is silent regarding the details of ownership and entitlement—limiting itself to what Rawls describes as “personal property.”25 25.Rawls, TJ, supra note 16, at 61; Rawls, JaF, supra note 10, at 114.Show More

The next possibility Scheffler calls “weak distributivism.”26 26.Scheffler, supra note 8, at 222 (emphasis omitted).Show More As he acknowledges, weak distributivism might appear to be an idiosyncratic, if not circular, possibility for Rawlsianism.27 27.Id. at 225.Show More The idea is this: first, a narrow, basic structure (the basic constitutional essentials and the system of tax and transfer) would be constructed to satisfy the demands of the two principles of justice, inclusive of the liberty principle and equality of opportunity. Then, one is free to add any private law construction that avoids worsening the position of the least well-off from the perspective of the baseline drawn by the initial construction.

Therefore, crucial to weak distributivism is that the selection of a conception of private law avoids “worsening the economic position of the least favoured members of society.”28 28.Id. at 222.Show More Constraining the range of the two principles of justice by excluding the private law from the initial construction and instead invoking the “not worsening test” is functionally equivalent to converting, solely for the private law, Rawls’s maximizing conception of the difference principle to a significantly weaker “sufficiency principle” analogous to the structure of the revised first principle of justice’s liberty construction.29 29.See Rawls, JaF, supra note 10, at 43.Show More This initial move creates a normatively arbitrary baseline in the initial set-up, as it is inattentive to the economic entitlements created by the private law.

Still, the choice of private law might be said to be “in” the basic structure, as it is constrained by the “no worsening” condition. The upshot is that this constraint, once satisfied, would leave the private law not constructed by the Rawlsian principles of justice, allowing that it might be “fixed in other ways.”30 30.Scheffler, supra note 8, at 222.Show More Scheffler recognizes that there is a baseline problem with respect to the “no worsening” constraint. In doing so, he aptly notes:

Suppose there is one way of designing contract law which, when the rest of the basic structure is properly designed, will maximise the position of the worst-off group. Relative to that baseline, any other way of designing contract law will worsen the position of the worst-off, and so any design that is non-optimal is ruled out. . . . And it is unclear why any other baseline would be appropriate.31 31.Id. at 225.Show More

Thus, the possibility exists that “weak distributivism” essentially collapses into strong distributivism.32 32.See id. (“But then, relative to that baseline, the weak distributivist requirement that contract law must not worsen the position of the worst-off is indistinguishable from the strong distributivist requirement that it must maximise the position of the worst off. . . . This means that there is a tendency for weak distributivism to slide in the direction of strong distributivism.”).Show More If this collapse can be somehow staved off, then ironically, weak distributivism, despite recognizing that private law is in the basic structure, may be in many ways analogous to the conventional view—which we and Scheffler reject—leaving Rawlsianism neutral with respect to a range of private law constructions.

Recognition of the baseline problem points to an even deeper concern. Weak distributivism contemplates the structure of contract and tort, without attention to the antecedent structure of the full range of property entitlements, which are fundamental to private law and are themselves a function, too, of taxation and transfer. Property, including the details of ownership and control, is itself unquestionably part of the basic structure and must be constructed according to the demands of the principles of justice. For this reason, there is a certain level of incoherence that runs through the position. Taxation and transfer require and define (respectively) entitlement baselines; these would include any rights to compensation, transfer, or exchange.

The conceptual distinction required by “weak distributivism” risks circularity. Given that private law defines and enforces entitlement baselines, the initial entitlement baseline cannot be constructed at the first step of the weak distributivist’s argument. The question of the basic structure is in no small measure the very question of economic entitlements; it would speak to the same thing. Importantly, the Rawlsian scheme is not concerned with traditional Anglo-American conceptions or doctrinal modules of the “private law” as a normative baseline. Rather, the focus is on the details of ownership and control, inclusive of personal security and transactions, governed by the two principles of justice defining who owns what and why and the details of such ownership. The weak distributivist compatibility strategy is unacceptable, given this incoherence.

In important and highly influential work, Arthur Ripstein,33 33.Ripstein, supra note 9, at 291, 293–94.Show More Samuel Freeman,34 34.Freeman, supra note 8, at 168.Show More and Gregory Keating35 35.Gregory C. Keating, Form and Substance in the “Private Law” of Torts, 14 J. Tort L. 45, 56–57 (2021).Show More have recently (re)addressed the relationship between Rawls and the private law and offered further accounts. While Ripstein’s view of the basic structure is contested, he has newly argued that the private law can remain conceptually independent of the two principles of justice. This is based on his commitment to the distinction between background justice—the domain of public law—which, for Ripstein, presupposes the idea of foreground justice, the domain of transactions. Samuel Freeman has argued, in agreement with us, that property, contracts, and much of tort law are within the basic structure, but he is skeptical of the role of the difference principle. Gregory Keating, too, has agreed that the private law is in the basic structure but holds that a form of empirical overlap may produce a form of non-principled compatibility. In what follows, we discuss these positions further.

In Private Wrongs, Arthur Ripstein aims to demonstrate compatibility between his largely backward-looking private law theory—fueled by comprehensive Kantian notions of freedom and responsibility—and Rawlsian justice.36 36.Ripstein, supra note 9, at 291.Show More Here, Ripstein appears to sidestep questions concerning the breadth of the basic structure.37 37.Id. (claiming that the “specifics of Rawls’s formulation” of the basic structure “need not concern us”).Show More But whether Ripstein holds that tort is inside or outside the basic structure, absent any stopping point akin to the “no worsening requirement” described by Scheffler, Ripstein’s private law construction is sufficiently independent of Rawls’s two principles of justice to render the distinction meaningless.

Ripstein distinguishes between background and foreground justice, where background justice is constituted by mandatory rules, constructed by the Rawlsian principles of justice, while foreground justice is the domain of the permissible voluntary or private sphere, governed by his preferred Kantian account of private law predicated on pre-institutional notions of freedom and responsibility.38 38.Id.Show More The purported demand for a private sphere, in Rawls, creates the needed space for compatibility.39 39.Id.Show More As interesting as this view is, it will not get Ripstein his independent “private” view of tort and contract. In the Rawlsian scheme, all such rules, whether constraint-imposing or liberty-allowing, are fixed constructions of the two principles of justice. Any underived distinction between background and foreground justice is off target; the principles of justice construct the very distinction in question. Such rules, then, cannot be altered in service to a “new” moralized conception of contract or tort. For Rawls, the same is true of the public/private distinction, which is not an underived starting place40 40.Kordana & Tabachnick, Belling the Cat, supra note 11, at 1288; Scheffler, supra note 8, at 233.Show More as may be found in other conceptions of liberalism, but instead the derived outcome of the construction. It would appear that Ripstein’s independent Kantian private law conception of tort and contract, derived from the re-introduction of “freedom” and “responsibility,” is not admissible at this stage. Such a (re)introduction would conflict with the Rawlsian construction, providing an alternative conception of the same.

In recent work, torts scholar Gregory Keating notes that significant areas of tort doctrine are distributive and welfare-oriented.41 41.Keating, supra note 35, at 97 (“We cannot understand or justify the law of torts without attending to the interests that it protects. . . . Our law of torts is intimately interwoven with administrative schemes, such as workers’ compensation, and with statutory regimes, such as zoning and direct risk regulation . . . .”).Show More He correctly recognizes that for Rawls, tort would be, contra the conventional view, “part of the basic structure, with its own distinctive role and concerns,”42 42.Id. at 57.Show More but importantly not walled off from the overall accident reduction scheme43 43.Id. at 97 (“‘Private law’ tort theorists also make too much of form when they present the legal category of tort as its own independent kingdom, walled off from surrounding legal fields.” (emphasis omitted)); id. at 86 (“The tort law of accidents can be wholly displaced by direct risk regulation and ‘social insurance’—as it has been in New Zealand. . . . The vulnerability of our law of torts to such eclipse casts doubt on the thought that tort law is an autonomous realm of ‘private law,’ governed by its own sui generis internal principles.” (emphasis omitted)).Show More and not directly read off of the difference principle.44 44.Id. at 57 (“For example, it would be opportunistic and objectionable to use the difference principle to determine the size of damage awards in private lawsuits.”).Show More

Keating, however, offers an (empirical) compatibilist possibility quite distinct from Ripstein’s approach. We agree with Keating’s rejection of the conventional view. But Keating may at points seem to be overly optimistic in discussing what might be even empirically compatible with a Rawlsian scheme as a matter of non-principled overlap. He remarks that the complete Rawlsian scheme of legal and political rules “is compatible with either enterprise responsibility schemes or the individual responsibility of ‘private law’ as Ripstein conceives it.”45 45.Id. at 95.Show More

The possibility of over-interpreting Keating looms large. Keating is addressing his argument to the possibility of empirical overlap in the construction of the ultimate scheme of legal rules, not to the principled commitment of the sort Ripstein offers.46 46.Id. at 96 (“The mistake would be to think that Rawls’ framework—or some other liberal theory of justice—mandates either ‘private law’ or a New Zealand scheme, or some intermediate arrangement, as a matter of first principles of justice. It does not. To make these choices, we need to supplement basic principles of justice with additional considerations and information.”).Show More There is an important distinction to make here: Rawlsianism might construct a right for individuals to bring suit or demand recourse, but such a right would not be constructed for the Kantian reasons of freedom and responsibility.

The right would instead be derived from security of the person, equality of opportunity, and economic distributive reasons. More comprehensive or Kantian conceptions would be too focused on conceptual independence, derived from freedom and responsibility, to be required at this stage of Rawlsian argument.47 47.Id. at 97; see also Christopher Heath Wellman & A. John Simmons, Is There a Duty to Obey the Law? 156 n.38 (2005) (noting self-referentially that discussion of Rawlsianism can be “aimed at a Rawls who is more Kantian than Rawls actually wished to be”).Show More But Keating may be overly optimistic of even empirical overlap, which seems unlikely to be robust given the Rawlsian scheme’s lack of commitment, for example, to the causal requirement or to backward-looking, “corrective” remedies.

Consider further possibilities. In various parts of Liberalism and Distributive Justice, especially Chapter Five, “Private Law and Rawls’s Principles of Justice, Rawls scholar Samuel Freeman provides an extensive discussion of Rawls and the private law. Freeman holds that the debate surrounding the narrowing of the basic structure owes to a mistake: an “infelicitous expression” on Rawls’s part.48 48.Freeman, supra note 8, at 194.Show More Freeman holds that the correct view of the basic structure is broad. He agrees that contract49 49.Id. at 174 (“That Rawls regards the principles of justice as applying to the law of contract . . . is pretty clearly suggested in his discussion of the principle of fairness.”).Show More and tort50 50.Id. at 189 (“Accordingly, unlike Ripstein, I think that more direct engagement with and application of the principles of justice, especially the first principle . . . is suitable for applying Rawls’s theory of justice to the details of a Rawlsian tort theory.”).Show More law are within the basic structure and are subject to construction by the principles of justice. But Freeman is somewhat skeptical of the role that the difference principle might play in the construction of tort law,51 51.Id. at 123 (“There are many social policies for which the difference principle does not appear to be the appropriate standard of assessment . . . [including] ordinary negligence and determinations of fault and remedies in non-economic torts . . . .”).Show More arguing that tort law is largely a first principle construction.52 52.Id. at 188–89.Show More

We too have extensively argued that a large part of Rawlsian accident management involves personal security as a first principle matter,53 53.Kordana & Tabachnick, Belling the Cat, supra note 11, at 1293.Show More but we also hold that a significant portion is an economic construction to be governed by the difference principle. We have called this the High Rawlsian position, consistent with the High Liberal position (ironically a term coined, as best we know, by Samuel Freeman).54 54.Samuel Freeman, Illiberal Libertarians: Why Libertarianism Is Not a Liberal View, 30 Phil. & Pub. Affs. 105, 106 (2002).Show More Freeman’s hesitance regarding the difference principle appears to derive from two main concerns: (1) an interpretation that such governance would result in decisions being “read off of” the difference principle in a direct (and unjust) manner,55 55.Freeman, supra note 8, at 123 (“Like determinations of fault and remedies in negligence cases, it would be unfair to require that assets between divorced spouses be divided so as to maximally benefit the least advantaged class . . . .”).Show More and (2) the idea that, for Freeman, torts are largely analogous to crimes; tort remedies are to respond to rights violations that should not have happened in the first instance, so they are (re)distributive, as opposed to distributive.56 56.Id. at 184–85.Show More

First, tort decisions, the very construction of the negligence standard, or the bounds of strict liability no more need to be “read-off” of the difference principle than do the rules of taxation. Tort law, and accident management more broadly, would find their home in an overall scheme that maximizes the position of the least well-off. That scheme is, of course, subject to the lexically prior liberty constraints governing security of the person. There is no commitment to any specific pre-ordained equity-oriented outcome. By analogy, the Rawlsian scheme would likely violate horizontal equity in taxation; there would be no antecedent commitment to a specified set of marginal income tax rates. The complete set of legal rules would be set in reference to the position of the least well-off. The selection ultimately is inter-schemic in order to best satisfy the requirements of the two principles of justice, not an intra-schemic reflection of equality as between individual people in rendering legal verdicts, whether in tort or taxation. Correspondingly, a poorer party surely need not necessarily prevail in civil litigation. The argument to the contrary is predicated on a misunderstanding.

Second, tort would provide security of the person consistent with sufficient liberty, but the difference principle would likely speak in part to the negligence standard; any selection between, for example, property and liability rule protection; the magnitude of honest industry; and importantly the question of who bears the cost of its attendant accidents (tragically, there always will be some). Further, tort helps define which externalities are to be internalized and which costs are to be associated with which activities.57 57.Calabresi, supra note 15, at 69, 144.Show More Much of this is distributive as opposed to redistributive or, contra Freeman, a backward-looking correction,58 58.Freeman, supra note 8, at 184.Show More setting initial baselines that will significantly affect the life-prospects of the least-well-off. Once sufficient basic liberty and opportunity are constructed, largely in terms of security of the person, the remainder would be subject to the difference principle, as opposed to, for example, notions of optimal deterrence as found in the economic analysis of law.

We will return to Freeman’s skepticism regarding the maximizing nature of the difference principle in Section III.B. But still, it is important to appreciate that the two principles of justice play different roles in what are traditionally considered different bodies of the private law, to the extent that they will invoke an economic construction. We noted above that the High Rawlsian position restricts the ability of the first principle of justice to construct any broad or robust economic entitlements. However, the first principle’s demand for security would necessitate a robust role in the accident reduction system. To the extent, for example, that the tort system provides for the delineation of risk and cost baselines pertaining to honest industry, both in protecting security of the person and maximizing the position of the least well-off, it would be constructed in service to the demands of the two principles of justice, in lexical priority.

II. Rawlsian Contractualism and the Private Law

Rawls offers a systems approach to legal and political institutions. One cannot simply construct the larger body of legal and political institutions without attention to the private law and then slip-in one’s preferred account of the substance of the private law.59 59.Kordana & Tabachnick, Rawls & Contract, supra note 2, at 621; Murphy, Artificial Morality, supra note 11, at 457 n.11 (noting Rawls proposed evaluating private law institutions on the basis of his two principles).Show More The introduction of a conceptually independent account of the private law will almost certainly upset the interworking of the system and its goals. For example, were a corrective justice-oriented account of tort to systematically and routinely require large payments from the least-well off to the better off due to negligence, it would violate the weak distributivist “no-worsening” condition.

Any rights of exchange (contract or gift), the system of accident reduction and compensation (tort), and taxation and transfer are, for Rawls, the very question of ownership, entitlement, and control. There is no pre-ordained commitment to traditional or doctrinal legal categories nor to a distinction between so-called “underlying” property rights and “transactional” rights, as might be found in some pre-institutional, doctrinal, Kantian, or Lockean accounts. Importantly, where a distributive maximand is in place, it is wholly indeterminate whether a rule imposing a fifty percent tax rate on income is to be described as a rule of tax, a rule of property, or a rule of contract.60 60.Kronman, supra note 1, at 501–05.Show More

Importantly, all entitlements need to be set in conjunction with an optimal tax rate associated with the specific maximand, the appropriately constrained difference principle. To do otherwise will create distortions from the perspective of the constrained difference principle that cannot, contra Kaplow and Shavell’s taxation and transfer thesis, simply be recuperated by adjustments in progressive marginal taxation rates without causing additional inefficiency deleterious to the position of the least well-off.61 61.Blankfein-Tabachnick & Kordana, supra note 5, at 34.Show More

For Rawls, ownership and control are to be constructed jointly as part of the system of entitlements constructed by the two principles of justice. They are the derived outcomes of the institutional construction, not the result of a direct appeal to a free-standing or underived set of first principles. To think otherwise is to significantly under-appreciate the Rawlsian project’s ambition in its rejection of traditional or doctrinal details of property and ownership and control. Rawls is offering a legal construction or “replacement” theory62 62.Rawls, TJ, supra note 16, at 95.Show More which is taken to be just by virtue of its original position (“OP”) derivation.

The selected scheme of legal and political rules is suffused with the principles of justice; new or exogenous fairness or justice-oriented objections to the scheme are misplaced at this stage of the argument. Such objections, coherently raised, must be addressed to the derivation of distributive principles themselves or the Rawlsian assumptions that constructed them. It is in this sense that Rawlsianism is importantly distributive, as opposed to re-distributive.63 63.Kordana & Tabachnick, Rawls & Contract, supra note 2, at 621; Murphy, Artificial Morality, supra note 11, at 457 n.11 (noting Rawls’s principles “do not obviously have room for values distinctively associated with private ordering”).Show More In our estimation, much of the worldwide allure and intellectual sensation surrounding Rawlsianism, for better or worse, owes to this very fact: the two principles of justice create afresh.

The principles of justice are addressed, at least, to legally enforceable interpersonal relationships. Were values associated with non-distributive conceptions of private law necessary to justice in the well-ordered society, representatives in the OP would have imposed such values upon the principles of justice themselves. To re-introduce such values at the stage of the legal construction would be to deviate from the very conception of justice derived in the OP.

True, the two principles of justice are not addressed to all normative matters, for example, aesthetic or romantic values. Still, it is important to note that the non-aesthetic aspects of, say, museum administration, such as endowment policy, taxation and nonprofit status, etc., would be regulated by the two principles of justice; so too would, by analogy, the non-academic, fiscal aspects of universities and the details of property ownership among life-partners, households, etc., during the pendency of their arrangements and in the context of separation or divorce. Even though Rawls’s two principles of justice do not speak to everything, the first principle of justice might be required to weigh-in on, say, a right to bequeath personal property, and would, too, constrain the difference principle in governing the tenets of religious doctrine within religious organizations as a matter of freedom of thought and conscience protected by the lexically prior first principle. The domain of non-applicability is quite narrow, indeed.

Current, conventional notions of marriage allow each partner a veto power, but do not require input from third-party stakeholders who might be affected (such as children, parents, and grandparents).64 64.John G. Bennett, Freedom and Enforcement: Comments on Ripstein, 92 Va. L. Rev. 1439, 1440–41 (2006).Show More A Rawlsian scheme would consider, although need not accept, the possibility of alternative arrangements in order to satisfy the demands of the two principles of justice. The structure of a legally binding ability to enter or exit civil commitments might be designed in service to the first principle of justice, while the second principle of justice might construct the conception of equality of opportunity and the economic nature of such relationships. But presumably some interpersonal dynamics of family or romantic life would remain open, as mandated by the first principle of justice. The same holds, by analogy, for the aesthetic evaluations necessary to a bona fide museum of fine art or the academic standards of a university.

The two principles of justice are forward-looking. The difference principle is maximizing a feature we discuss further in Part III, subject to lexically prior constraints of liberty and equality of opportunity. Given these features of Rawlsianism, there is little indeterminacy or non-mandated “openness” in the selected scheme of legal and political rules. In discussing institutional design, Rawls draws an analogy between the rules of taxation and contract law,65 65.Rawls, Political Liberalism 268 (2005) [hereinafter Rawls, PL].Show More holding that the operative bodies of both are part of background (i.e., distributive) justice and, therefore, subject to the principles of justice. Rawls arguably invokes notions of “simplicity” and “practicality,” consistent with the principles of justice, as a mere guidepost for institutional design, perhaps constructing rules that apply to end-state users: individual citizens.66 66.Scheffler, supra note 8, at 221.Show More But if this is correct, despite all the controversy, it is not clear where “openness” sufficient to the construction of exogenous conceptions of private law might be found nor how an appeal to such demands might be motivated at this stage.

While it is true that the two principles of justice are range-limited, it is inconceivable to hold, as the conventional view once did, that the operative function of any private law construction should be understood as other than under the domain of the two principles of justice. Indeed, Scheffler describes it as intellectually feeble.67 67.Id. at 233.Show More This seems particularly clear if one considers the role such operative bodies of law would play in the provision of security of the person and in defining markets and the free and fair terms of cooperation and economic exchange.

Once the Rawlsian scheme of legal and political rules is selected, compatibility between Rawlsianism and non-distributive mandates concerning any “private law” construction seem ill-motivated. Further still, the re-introduction of such private law conceptions risks threatening the very framework Rawls set out to devise. The Rawlsian ideal is to construct a complete set of just legal and political institutions for the basic structure of society, acceptable even to property skeptics. Independent accounts of the private law are competing approaches often derived from a moralized account of the Anglo-American common law,68 68.E.g., Elizabeth Sepper & Deborah Dinner, Sex in Public, 129 Yale L.J. 78 (2019) (discussing the history of public values in the common law).Show More as in the New Private Law Theory. As such, they speak to the same thing; they offer a competing conception of the very same concepts. Importantly, for Rawls there still may be constructed private law modules,69 69.David Blankfein-Tabachnick, Maximizing Intellectual Property: Optimality, Synchronicity, and Distributive Justice, 94 St. John’s L. Rev. 1, 51 (2020).Show More representing, for example, innovation policy, accident management, commercial reliance, etc., but these modules need not pattern our conventional doctrinal law of intellectual property, tort, or contract, respectively.

Return now to the question of compatibility with traditional private law or ex post private law conceptions. The problem, as we see it, runs even deeper still. The Rawlsian OP-derived construction is robust. For Rawls, “justice” is the sector of the concept of “right” that encompasses prominent social, political, and legal institutions.70 70.Rawls, TJ, supra note 16, at 95 (“[T]o establish a complete conception of right, . . . parties in the original position are to choose in a definite order not only a conception of justice but also principles to go with each major concept falling under the concept of right.”).Show More Importantly, even the social institution of promising and promise keeping is governed by the OP-derived two principles of justice.71 71.Id. at 303–04 (“I shall not regard promising as a practice which is just by definition . . . There are many variations of promising just as there are of the law of contract. Whether the particular practice . . . is just remains to be determined by the principles of justice.”).Show More

Further, it is not only the conception of justice that is OP-derived for Rawls. Any remaining sectors of the concept of “right,”72 72.Seana Shiffrin suggests, in a non-Rawlsian context, that contract law may be derived from principles of right rather than solely from principles of justice. Seana Valentine Shiffrin, The Divergence of Contract and Promise, 120 Harv. L. Rev. 708, 716 (2007).Show More we are told, “are . . . relatively few in number and have a determinate relation to each other.”73 73.Rawls, TJ, supra note 16, at 95.Show More It is true that we are neither told what the sectors of rightness might be, nor are we given the content of the principles for each sector. But we are, importantly, given the procedure by which they are to be derived, the OP.74 74.Id.Show More So, the ultimate construction is conceived of as “rightness as fairness.”75 75.Id. (“[T]he broader notion of rightness as fairness is to be understood as a replacement for existing conceptions.”).Show More It seems unlikely that any such OP derived principles would magically construct Anglo-American private law or have space for something much akin to it. Rawls himself lists as candidates, OP-derived, “principles for individuals,” and “the law of nations.”76 76.Id. at 93–94.Show More Once one adds those to the principles for institutions, it is hard to imagine what might be left.

Rawls discusses principles for individuals, inclusive of the OP-derived “natural duties.” But for Rawls, the natural duties are not natural in the ordinary sense77 77.George Klosko, Political Obligation and the Natural Duties of Justice, 23 Phil. & Pub. Affs. 251, 254 (1994); Wellman & Simmons, supra note 47, at 156 n.38 (“[T]he natural duties actually discussed by Rawls are not ‘natural’ in any very strong sense, but are only the ‘postinstitutional’ moral duties that original position reasoners would select to bind themselves in their subsequent interactions.”).Show More of the term—they are not exogenous of the OP-construction. So, both the principles that apply to individuals and those that apply to social institutions are OP-derived constructions.78 78.Rawls, TJ, supra note 16, at 95.Show More As such, they serve as a “replacement” for an ordinary language account of the normative concepts in question.79 79.Id. (“[T]he concept of something’s being right is the same as, or better, may be replaced by, the concept of its being in accordance with the principles that in the original position would be acknowledged to apply to things of its kind.”).Show More And to avoid conflict, the two sets of principles, those that apply to institutions and to individuals, operate in conjunction and must not conflict, which explains the demand for the complete OP derivation.80 80.Id. at 294 (“[T]he choice of principles for individuals is . . . simplified [since] principles for institutions have already been adopted. The feasible alternatives are . . . narrowed . . . to those that constitute a coherent conception of duty and obligation when taken together with the two principles of justice. . . . [L]et us suppose . . . the choice of the principle of utility . . . as the standard for the acts of individuals. . . . [This] would lead to an incoherent conception of right. The criteria for institutions and individuals do not fit together properly.”).Show More The principles of justice, those for institutions, are required first81 81.Id. at 93 (“The important thing is that the various principles are to be adopted in a definite sequence . . . .”); id. (“[T]he principles for the basic structure of society are to be agreed to first, principles for individuals next . . .”).Show More to set needed baselines without which notions of “harm” or “obligation,” for example, would be incoherent or lack normative force.82 82.Id. (“[O]bligations presuppose principles for social forms” and duties for individuals “presuppose such principles . . . .”).Show More

Given the demands of the OP-derived two principles of justice and the OP-derived principles that apply to individuals, it is not at all clear where (conflicting) ordinary normative notions might fit and even more importantly, why they would be needed in a theory of this kind.83 83.Id. at 95 (“[T]hat principles for institutions are chosen first shows the social nature of the virtue of justice, its intimate connection with social practices . . . .”); id. (“The intuitive idea is this: the concept of something’s being right is the same as, or better, may be replaced by, the concept of its being in accordance with the principles that in the original position would be acknowledged to apply to things of its kind. I do not interpret this concept of right as providing an analysis of the meaning of the term ‘right’ as normally used in moral contexts. It is not meant as an analysis of the concept of right in the traditional sense. Rather, the broader notion of rightness as fairness is to be understood as a replacement for existing conceptions.”).Show More The Rawlsian OP construction imposes all necessary justice-oriented requirements upon the principles of justice, which in turn construct legal institutions. Any appeal to “everyday” or pre-institutional normative values or the Anglo-American common law itself is ill at home with the mandates of the Rawlsian construction.84 84.Murphy, Artificial Morality, supra note 11, at 457 n.11.Show More Importantly, common law doctrine or moralized accounts cannot serve as the normative baseline. While it is true that the Rawlsian system does ultimately admit of reflective equilibrium,85 85.Rawls, TJ, supra note 16, at 95–96.Show More this does not open the floodgates to insert antecedently desired moralized legal or political modules.

Consider, as an instructive example, how private law might construct the role of gift-giving in a Rawlsian system. It could be quite constrained. There is no guarantee that, post-institutionally, persons would be “free” to act in accord with (pre-institutional) notions of beneficence. Gift-giving could upset entitlements as defined and implemented by the two principles of justice. Such transfers could be closed in certain settings as a direct matter; for example, it might be instrumental to the scheme to limit or eliminate donor influence at charities. In addition, gift-giving might be taxed. This might include taxation of the donor, the recipient, or both and need not pattern the current U.S. tax code or the “Duberstein test.”86 86.See 26 U.S.C. § 102; Comm’r v. Duberstein, 363 U.S. 278, 287–88 (1960).Show More This tax rate could equal or even exceed 100%, perhaps on the notion that the donor gains “sway” or “sycophant appeal” while losing some welfare, while the recipient, at the same time, gains welfare. Or, if progressive taxation were instrumental to the scheme, it would be unlikely that donors in an intra-familial setting be allowed a deduction, lest high-earners be able to “level down” their incomes through donations to lower-income family members.

Now, consider the role of “openness” in a Rawlsian system. Rawlsian entitlements might instrumentally construct some space in which individuals would govern (post-institutional) liberty to transact voluntarily. Such openness would be mandatory. As such, it could not be reconstructed87 87.Felipe Jimenez, Contracts, Markets, and Justice, 71 U. Toronto L.J. 144, 162 (2021) (discussing optimistically a hypothetical compatibility between distributive principles and the given terms of contract doctrine).Show More by the demands of an alternative theory,88 88.E.g., Zhong Xin Tang, Where the Action Is: Macro and Micro Justice in Contract Law, 83 Mod. L. Rev. 725, 727 (2020) (providing an elegant account of the macro/micro realms and advocating for a compatibility between constraints of reciprocity, notions of justice in transaction, etc.).Show More say, Friedian contract law.89 89.Charles Fried, Contract as Promise: A Theory of Contractual Obligation 1 (2d ed. 2015).Show More Further, such alternative conceptions of contract law would not be deployable as warrant for broadening the openness in the Rawlsian system. The boundaries of openness are determined by the two principles of justice; any demands for a distinct range of openness derived from an alternative theory of contract would conflict.

III. The Possibility of Incompleteness: Scheffler’s Lacunae Hypothesis

While Scheffler agrees that the “private law” is properly understood to be within the basic structure, he raises the hypothetical possibility that distributive principles may be insufficient to fully construct an acceptable system of private law. The hypothesis is that there are aspects of a sufficiently satisfactory private law, and perhaps criminal law, that are just not about distributive justice. This hypothetical insufficiency would provide a demand for the operation of additional non-distributivist principles to construct the aspects of private law. As Scheffler points out, notably similar lines of questioning can be found in important work by both John Goldberg90 90.John C.P. Goldberg, Introduction: Pragmatism and the New Private Law, 125 Harv. L. Rev. 1640, 1660–61 (2012).Show More and Seana Shiffrin.91 91.Shiffrin, supra note 72, at 712.Show More But Goldberg and Shiffrin are non-Rawlsians and offer theories quite distinct from Rawls. Still, the issue is this: What if additional principles, drawn from the concept of justice, are needed for a satisfactory private law construction—values whose principles we have not been given by Rawls?92 92.Scheffler, supra note 8, at 224, 232 (discussing possibility the two principles of justice might “threaten . . . the realisation of ‘the important values expressed by free and fair agreements.’”).Show More

Yet recall that the OP-derived principles of justice construct the private law as a function of the objective index of the primary goods, with attention to the social value of self-respect, in contrast to utilitarianism. This alone would go a great distance to slow the line of questioning, were the concern that Rawsianism may bear some of utilitarianisms’ alleged shortcomings surrounding, say, a purportedly impoverished account of promise keeping. Where exactly might the insufficiency lie? The Rawlsian OP, itself, is the “modeled” conclusion to a complex foundationally deontic argument predicated upon underived, pre-theoretic notions of human (a.) freedom and rationality and (b.) equality. Then, consider the OP-derived two principles of justice that provide a constructed account of (c.) balanced basic liberty, (d.) equality of opportunity, (e.) equality and efficiency in economic relations, (f.) the lexical ordering among them, and their implementation measured in terms of (g.) the objective index of the primary goods.93 93.Kordana & Tabachnick, Belling the Cat, supra note 11, at 1286–87.Show More It is difficult to imagine what more is needed qua a theory of justice of this kind, particularly with respect to the purported incompleteness of legal institutions.

One is always free to raise high-order objections, whether to the two principles of justice as an incomplete or objectionable OP-derivation or object to the OP itself. But a danger of the skeptical line of questioning regarding “insufficiency” is that it may encourage getting things backward. The substance of Anglo-American private law is neither primitive nor the correct normative baseline for Rawlsianism. Private law constructions are the outcome of inter-schemic comparisons among complete schemes of legal and political institutions.

But Scheffler poses the higher-order concern:

If private law belongs to the basic structure, and if the role of principles of justice is to regulate the basic structure, and if principles of distributive justice . . . do not suffice to regulate private law, then there must be some other principles that regulate private law, and they too must be principles of justice for the basic structure.94 94.Scheffler, supra note 8, at 232.Show More

Scheffler’s hypothetical concern is that Rawls has been silent on this issue, and if there were a need for such additional principles, such silence leaves lacunae in the Rawlsian system. But Scheffler’s suggestion is that such hypothetical lacunae would derive, not from openness in the maximizing system as others have held, but from a potential conceptual incompleteness in Rawlsianism. That is, the possibility that distributive justice is not sufficient to construct a satisfactory conception of the private law.95 95.Id. at 228–29 (considering the possibility “that the terms of cooperation already mentioned are incomplete. Private law is not to be guided solely by the need to [satisfy the two principles of justice]. There are additional provisions that also have a role to play.”).Show More

For Scheffler, rectifying any hypothetical incompleteness would require additional principles and an account of how they are to function consistently among the existing principles of justice. But were there such a need, Rawls has been silent. As Scheffler recognizes, “we have not been told what [they] are.”96 96.Id. at 232.Show More But, still, we have been told quite a lot—against a backdrop of Rawls’s property-skepticism—about the justice-suffused principles of justice that, in the alternative, would govern the private law. If one finds the resulting scheme unsatisfactorily incomplete, that is, containing lacunae, that would be grounds for turning to another, non-Rawlsian approach to the private law, likely one grounded in pre-institutional principles of property entitlement.

But were Rawls’s silence, in fact, revelatory of incompleteness—as opposed to the more obvious explanation, a lack of necessity—we have been given the procedure by which principles are to be constructed, namely the OP. Whatever the content of the as yet non-existent principles, it is unlikely that additional principles that would construct conventional, doctrinal, or ex post conceptions of the private law would survive the OP and be consistent with what exists. Constructing additional principles that (1) do not conflict with what we have, such that they (2) do not simply provide a competing account of the same is a difficult needle to thread.

Consider just how difficult it would be: the creation of a sector of justice, distinct from the domain of the two principles of justice, which are taken to cover security of the person in terms of liberty, equality of opportunity, and the construction of economic relations. True, an additional principle, lexically ordered, is conceivable; perhaps a principle imposing something akin to “choice sensitivity,” “responsibility,” “voluntarism,” or even expansive “private ownership.” But such a principle, specifically addressing private ordering of, for example, the account of private property rights, the primacy of the outcomes of consensual exchange, rights to exclude, contract, etc., would likely be either (1) addressed to the same subject as the difference principle and inevitably create conflict, or (2) require a very stringent lexical ordering to avoid conflict. Rawls has not always been so stringent in lexical ordering, shifting away from the liberty principle as maximizing to a sufficiency principle, significantly hampering the difference principle’s domain. But adding such new constraints to the scheme would inevitably lower the provision of primary goods to the least well-off. Such hampering may potentially even create a class of the “justifiably poor,” if the difference principle’s lexical subordination were to prevent the “grossing up” of shares that were reduced in service to the new, antecedent principle(s). The possibility of a shipwreck would appear to loom large. While tinkering with the Rawlsian system is worth considering, as one should not be driven to Rawlsian fundamentalism, this approach does seem to be striking out in a rather non-Rawlsian direction.

Still, it is true that Rawls writes of “free” and “fair” markets, at least once noting that “straightaway” we need an account of what “free” and “fair” mean.97 97.Rawls, PL, supra note 65, at 266.Show More But do we have reason to doubt these terms would be constructions of the two principles of justice? The principles provide an account of the very same. Here, Rawls is responding to the “free market” or Lockean argument associated with Robert Nozick.98 98.Id.Show More It would be unusual if Rawls had intended an account of “free” and “fair” other than one derived from the two principles of justice.99 99.Elizabeth Anderson, The Ethical Limitations of the Market, 6 Econ. & Phil. 179, 182 (1990) (discussing the normative structure of markets).Show More It would be further surprising if Rawls had offered a more Lockean approach to the “market” than the conception constructed by the two principles of justice in one of Rawls’s few responses to Nozick.

But Scheffler is clear that his suggestion of incompleteness is merely hypothetical. He leaves open the possibility that Rawls has given us enough for a theory of this kind and more specifically enough to know that Rawlsianism, would, on this account, be in principled conflict with independent conceptions of the private law, e.g., the corrective justice conception of tort or the will theory of contracts.100 100.Scheffler, supra note 8, at 234 (“We may decide that such principles are complete, and that our institutions are to be guided solely by distributive considerations. . . . Alternatively we may decide that they are not complete . . . .”).Show More It is unclear that we have been betrayed by silence.

In their recent and stimulating book on tort doctrine and civil recourse, Recognizing Wrongs, John Goldberg and Benjamin Zipursky touch on Scheffler’s H.L.A. Hart lecture. They interpret Scheffler and Rawls as requiring that an account of justice must have “something to say about the law of torts” and agreeing that private law would properly be understood as within the Rawlsian basic structure.101 101.John C.P. Goldberg & Benjamin C. Zipursky, Recognizing Wrongs 14 (2020).Show More While we agree (1) that the private law is within the basic structure, contra the conventional view, and (2) that it seems inevitable that the Rawlsian scheme would need to manage accidents, we caution, again, that this need not entail critical formal features of Anglo-American tort law. Rawlsianism would seem to require an accident management system, but not necessarily conventional “tort law;” recall Keating’s instructive remarks on, for example, the New Zealand accident scheme.

But Goldberg & Zipursky are doctrinal in their approach to tort law.102 102.Id. at 355 (mentioning “the nature of private rights of action” as a key feature of tort law); id. at 228 (“[P]art of our aim here is to capture lawyerly understandings of the common law of torts.”); id. at 258 (contrasting their approach with that of Dworkin and Posner and stating that they do not “suppose that courts are engaged in the task of crafting optimal rules or making the law the best it can be”).Show More We agree that the ultimate Rawlsian scheme would likely provide individuals an avenue for redress, which may even be basic in the Rawlsian sense103 103.Id. at 30.Show More as a matter of security of the person, but the structure and form that avenue might take remains to be determined by the two principles of justice. While it is true that accounts associated with the “New Private Law Theory” may have a connection to justice in ordinary parlance, this is not the Rawlsian conception.

For Rawls, absent the sort of OP-derived revision Scheffler hypothesizes, the Rawlsian scheme would have to make do with liberty, equality of opportunity, and economic equality in the construction of tort rules. Out of fairness to Rawls, this does go a good deal further than the ordinary language use of the term “distributive justice,” typically limited to the economic distribution.104 104.Id. at 353 (noting Rawls is “frequently miscast as exclusively being a theorist of distributive justice” and commenting on the potentially “misleading” nature of characterizing the liberty-oriented first principle of justice as distributive).Show More Given Rawls’s more expansive account, it is not clear that distributive justice would need to be given lexical priority over other forms of justice in ordinary parlance.105 105.Cf. Goldberg, supra note 90, at 1661 & n.110 (arguing that principles of private law need to be accommodated with distributive justice rather than be lexically subordinate to distributive justice).Show More

IV. Reciprocity, Fair Terms of Cooperation, and the Difference Principle

From the broadest perspective, the two principles of justice represent the normative value of what Rawls describes as “reciprocity,” or what can be described in lay terms as the fair terms of social cooperation. The “difference principle,” maximizing the position of the least well-off, constructs the economic aspects of the complete scheme of legal and political rules.

Here, one might draw a distinction between post-institutional entitlement and the more universal pre-political value of human equality and worth. For Rawls, the concepts of entitlement and ownership are constructed by legal and political rules, instrumentally in service to the two principles of justice. Deep notions of freedom and equality for Rawls are universal, or pre-political; they lie behind the construction of the OP and, correspondingly, the derivation of two principles of justice.

A. The Rawlsian Systems Approach

The relationship between the two principles of justice and Rawls’s views concerning the value of reciprocity has caused, in our view, undue disagreement in the literature. The disagreement has called into question whether Rawlsianism is best understood as a maximizing theory and may disguise how it is best distinguished from welfarism.

The Rawlsian aim is to produce a “systems” theory in contrast with what he takes to be the distributively flawed utilitarian or welfarist approach to the evaluation of social institutions. Rawls distinguishes his approach from the welfarist approach associated with utilitarianism or the economic analysis of law. Importantly, Rawls’s two principles of justice bear a maximizing component, which is, as we say, taken in lexical priority and does not aggregate value, in the same manner one finds in utilitarianism or law and economics.

Further, Rawlsianism ranks institutions according to their provision of an objective index of primary goods, as opposed to welfarism or wealth-maximization, which measure value in subjective “preference fulfillment” or monetary terms, respectively. In distinguishing his conception of distributive justice from utilitarianism, Rawls points out that the two principles of justice represent the abstract ideal of “reciprocity” or the “fair terms of cooperation,” as distinct from objectionable aggregating theories.

From these observations, however, it does not follow that the difference principle, over its proper range of application, is not correctly understood as a maximizing principle. Instead, the difference principle is best understood as a domain-specific maximizing principle which embodies a component of the complete conception of reciprocity, in conjunction with lexically prior values. That is, the difference principle sets the economic baselines required for a coherent evaluation of the fair terms of cooperation. The difference principle is not a proxy for the value of social reciprocity, rather, the difference principle is a component of the two principles of justice that concretely define the value of reciprocity or, in ordinary language, the fair terms of cooperation. In our view, the maximizing nature of the difference principle seals in the conception of justice, rendering the system impervious to alternative conceptions. It sucks the air out of the metaphorical room.

B. Freeman and Conceptions of Economic Reciprocity

Given the role that “maximizing” plays in our account, we address the suggestion that the difference principle may not be best understood as a maximizing principle. In what follows, we (1) discuss Samuel Freeman’s important claims that the difference principle may be best understood, in the first instance, as a non-maximizing (potentially) intra-schemic relational principle. We then discuss (2) the role of the primary goods, as opposed to wealth or subjective preference fulfillment, as the correct metric for evaluating private law constructions, and the lexical priority of liberty and opportunity over the difference principle, and finally (3) what we take to be the correct Rawlsian view of “reciprocity” or the fair terms of cooperation.

In recent and important work, Samuel Freeman has discussed the Rawlsian difference principle and the idea of reciprocity.106 106.Freeman, supra note 8, at 107.Show More For Freeman, the difference principle is not to be understood as imposing a maximizing demand, but instead as the expression of the value of reciprocity or the fair terms of cooperation. But Freeman analyzes the idea of reciprocity somewhat in isolation and appears to (re)evaluate it separately from (1) the lexically prior liberty and opportunity constraints of the two principles of justice and (2) the set of institutional rules and entitlements that ultimately instantiate the very conception of reciprocity in concrete terms.

Our concern derives from the idea that Freeman may be reintroducing a new conception of reciprocity addressed to the wrong level. The abstract conception of reciprocity must ultimately impose specific substantive constraints on legal institutions or construct finite or specific legal rules via the two principles of justice. Freeman proposes a conception of the difference principle as an intra-schemic “relational” principle, as opposed to a maximizing one. In his estimation, this conception better instantiates a conception of reciprocity.

Freeman, in contrast to our view, holding that Rawls views the difference principle itself as a principle of reciprocity,107 107.Id. at 125 (citing Rawls, JaF, supra note 10, at 64).Show More goes on to argue that this implies that the difference principle is non-consequentialist and non-maximizing.108 108.Id. at 125, 186.Show More Freeman argues that “the justice of distributions to the least advantaged [is] decided by how well off they are compared with the most advantaged.”109 109.Id. at 125.Show More That is, the difference principle is an intra-schemic relational principle. But can this be right? True, Rawls is concerned with reciprocity, but notions of reciprocity are partially embedded in the (maximizing) difference principle itself. In other words, for Rawlsianism, the two principles of justice define the fair and just (or free and fair); they are suffused with the notion of reciprocity. Reciprocity is not to be reduced to the difference principle nor reintroduced as a separate intra-schemic, relational notion at the level of applying the difference principle. In our view, intra-schemic reciprocity is a derived outcome of the inter-schemic selection, not a starting place.

In rejecting the maximizing conception of the difference principle, Freeman provides an example of a society with a minimum share of $40,000. The possibility of achieving a $42,000 minimum share exists but should be rejected if it were to entail “substantial inequalities that are unjust.”110 110.Id.Show More Consider, perhaps, that the $42,000 minimum scheme contains considerably more billionaires than the $40,000 scheme. Yet concerns about that would seem to have been solved by the difference principle, properly understood and applied. We are evaluating shares in primary goods, not dollars. The former includes the social value of self-respect.

Freeman is correct that the (narrow) monetary package component of the (more robust) total package of primary goods received by the least well-off may expand or contract as between competing schemes of (selected) legal and political institutions. So, for the economist measuring solely in dollars, true, the Rawlsian scheme appears to be non-maximizing. But the difference principle is maximizing, subject to prior lexical constraints, in terms of the position of the least well-off in the total provision of primary goods.

By analogy, given that primary goods include security of the person, the Rawlsian difference principle would move away from an aggregating utilitarian scheme, in favor of a scheme with a greater demand for personal security. Given that one is maximizing in terms of primary goods, as opposed to dollars, security would not be completely traded away in favor of purely monetary shares. Presumably this would shrink the monetary component of the primary goods package available to members of the class of the least well-off. For example, the Rawlsian scheme might include more personal security, but smaller monetary shares, than the utilitarian scheme. Again, the two principles of justice—evaluated in terms of their provision of primary goods—provide, for Rawls, the account of reciprocity between persons and the fair terms of cooperation. Freeman here aims to (re)impose an alternative conception of equality (i.e., lower income disparity) than the two principles of justice would allow, while at the same time limiting the conception of reciprocity to the difference principle.

Freeman’s intra-schemic concern seems reminiscent of an objection to Rawls from the perspective of a more aggressive form of egalitarianism; namely, G.A. Cohen’s critique of the difference principle. That is, that the difference principle’s maximizing demands are objectionable, given Cohen’s commitment to a lower quantum of income disparity within the selected scheme.111 111.G.A. Cohen, Incentives, Inequality, and Community, The Tanner Lectures on Human Values 268 (May 21 & 23, 1991) (“I question [the difference principle’s] application in defense of special money incentives to talented people. . . . [T]he idea that an inequality is justified if, through the familiar incentive mechanism, it benefits the badly off is more problematic than Rawlsians suppose . . . .”).Show More It is hard to see how representatives in the OP, maximizing self-interest and precluded from reasoning from envy112 112.Rawls, TJ, supra note 16, at 131.Show More or comprehensive doctrine, might have grounds to object to the maximizing conception of the difference principle. Rawls is, after all, a liberal whose chief goal is a sustained critique of the distributive flaws in utilitarianism. He is not independently committed to an intra-schemic relational conception of egalitarianism.113 113.Id. at 130–31 (“If there are inequalities in income and wealth, and differences in authority and degrees of responsibility, that work to make everyone better off in comparison with the benchmark of equality, why not permit them? . . . Thus the basic structure should allow these inequalities so long as these improve everyone’s situation, including that of the least advantaged, provided that they are consistent with equal liberty and fair opportunity.”).Show More

Consider the chart Rawls provides on page sixty-two of Justice as Fairness: A Restatement:

Line chart

Description automatically generated

The y-axis is the least advantaged group; x, the most advantaged group; D represents the difference principle; N, the Nash point; B is Benthamite utilitarianism; F is feudalism and the J-J line is the highest equal justice point touched by the D. Here, Rawls is clearly aiming at maximizing the position of the least well-off (see point D) and demonstrating how this involves some sacrifice by the most advantaged group (cf. point B), while maximizing the position of the least advantaged group.

It is important to note that the chart compares the optimal application of alternative distributive principles. Rawls, for expository purposes, is comparing principles bearing differing axiologies (i.e., value systems) in order to amalgamate these principles on a single chart. But one must take care not to over-interpret the significance of the reductionist comparison for purposes of understanding whether the difference principle is maximizing. Rawls clearly interprets the difference principle as maximizing the position of the least advantaged group on the y-axis.

The upshot is that while Rawlsianism does not invoke maximization regarding monetary shares—in this Freeman would be absolutely correct—the theory is, nevertheless, maximizing. Once sufficient basic liberty, in respect of the two moral powers, and equality of opportunity are established, the correct comparison is among competing sets of institutions in their capacity to maximize the position of the least well-off. While this is not the account typically found in the economic analysis of law, it is nevertheless a maximizing and consequentialist theory, if a constrained one. A commitment to any independent or newly advanced intra-schemic relational conception of economic equality would appear unmotivated, given the full Rawlsian conception of reciprocity. This, too, is not merely a scholastic exercise. Interpreting Rawls as other than maximizing in making the final inter-schemic selection among completing sets of legal and political rules would, in our view, upset the (derived) account of intra-schemic reciprocity that owes to the selection itself.

Conclusion

There has been a welcome academic shift in perspective with regard to Rawls and the private law. This shift points to the conclusion that despite decades of international debate, there is a Rawlsian account of the private law satisfactory to contractualist theory of its kind. If we are correct, this account conflicts with important aspects of alternative approaches to private law, theoretical and doctrinal. Whether the Rawlsian account is fully satisfactory to those committed to alternative approaches is an open question; but if not, that is, in our view, a question that should be addressed to the acceptability of Rawlsianism itself.

  1. See, e.g., Bruce A. Ackerman, Social Justice in the Liberal State 195 (1980); David Lyons, Ethics and the Rule of Law 131–32 (1984) (asserting “the principles of justice” “do not apply to private arrangements and transactions”); Anthony T. Kronman, Contract Law and Distributive Justice, 89 Yale L.J. 472, 474, 477 (1980) (noting the “unconcern with the distributive consequences of . . . private arrangements”).
  2. Kevin A. Kordana & David H. Tabachnick, Rawls and Contract Law, 73 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 598, 599–600 (2005) [hereinafter Kordana & Tabachnick, Rawls & Contract].
  3. Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell, Why the Legal System Is Less Efficient than the Income Tax in Redistributing Income, 23 J. Legal Stud. 667, 667–69 (1994).
  4. Id.
  5. David Blankfein-Tabachnick & Kevin A. Kordana, Kaplow and Shavell and the Priority of Income Taxation and Transfer, 69 Hastings L.J. 1 (2017). In outlining what he terms the three most crucial scholarly “caveats” to Kaplow and Shavell’s argument, Guttentag writes,A second caveat to the double-distortion presumption has to do with property rights. . . . Blankfein-Tabachnick and Kordana argue that taking property rights as a given is deeply problematic for the double-distortion presumption because property rights themselves are a creation of the legal system. Moreover, property rights have significant effects on the distribution of income and wealth.Michael D. Guttentag, Law, Taxes, Inequality, and Surplus, 102 B.U. L. Rev. 1329, 1336–37 (2022).
  6. Blankfein-Tabachnick & Kordana, supra note 5, at 8; Kevin A. Kordana & David H. Tabachnick, Taxation, the Private Law, and Distributive Justice, 23 Soc. Phil. & Pol’y 142, 163 (2006) (“Kaplow and Shavell appear to assume the existence of an underlying system of property ownership and free markets. [The] issue, however, is the very question of the form that property rules should take; that is, we are interested in the question of whether the equity-oriented values that differing theorists hold are best met through tax and transfer, or through (in part) the rules of property law. Thus, it is not clear that Kaplow and Shavell’s discussion, which compares tax and transfer to a tort rule (in isolation) and concludes that tax and transfer is superior in terms of economic efficiency, would (also) apply to the question of the underlying set of property rules.”).
  7. Kordana & Tabachnick, Rawls & Contract, supra note 2, at 632 (“Our conclusions are bold. . . . [C]ontrary to the conventionally held narrow conception, contract law is within the basic structure . . . [and] the door is open for a deeper understanding of the role that private law plays in Rawlsian political philosophy—it is no longer accurate to believe that Rawlsianism is silent on matters of contract and private ordering . . . .”). Shapiro, for example, notes the similarity between our position in Kordana & Tabachnick, Rawls & Contract, supra note 2, and the recent scholarship, aptly drawing conclusions from the perspective of the new paradigm, taking its baseline as given. Matthew A. Shapiro, Distributing Civil Justice, 109 Geo. L.J. 1473, 1531 (2021). “Rawls’s theory thus does not defuse the conflicts between distributive justice and the liberal state’s other roles so much as deny them, by assigning distributive justice effective, if not formal, priority over other imperatives.” Id. at 1532. He then contrasts the new baseline with that of the former “conventional” view, ably recognizing the conflict within that view, and holding that it is “[o]nly by diluting the requirements of distributive justice” that one might “manage to harmonize them with [backward-looking or deontic] dispute resolution and rights enforcement.” Id. at 1533.
  8. See, e.g., Samuel Scheffler, Distributive Justice, the Basic Structure and the Place of Private Law, H.L.A. Hart Memorial Lecture (May 2014), in 35 Oxford J. Legal Stud. 213, 233 (2015); Samuel Freeman, Liberalism and Distributive Justice 168, 192–93 (2018) (arguing Rawls’s principles apply to the private law); Richard L. Revesz, Regulation and Distribution, 93 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 1489, 1518 (2018) (asserting distributional concerns, not just wealth maximization, should play a broader role in regulation).
  9. E.g., Arthur Ripstein, Private Wrongs 291 (2016); Freeman, supra note 8, at 185; Zachary Liscow, Note, Reducing Inequality on the Cheap: When Legal Rule Design Should Incorporate Equity as Well as Efficiency, 123 Yale L.J. 2478, 2486–87 (2014).
  10. John Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement 42–43 (2001) [hereinafter Rawls, JaF] (“The two principles of justice [state] (a) Each person has the same indefeasible claim to a fully adequate scheme of equal basic liberties . . . and (b) Social and economic inequalities are to satisfy two conditions: first, they are to be attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair equality of opportunity; and second, they are to be to the greatest benefit of the least-advantaged members of society (the difference principle).”).
  11. As we noted supra note 1, Bruce Ackerman, David Lyons, and Anthony Kronman held the conventional or narrow view that private law lies outside the basic structure. But cf. Kronman, supra note 1, at 475 (suggesting that Rawls should not have narrowed). Scheffler posits that Ripstein views private law as lying within the basic structure, Scheffler, supra note 8, at 232 (“Suppose we accept that, although private law is part of the basic structure, there is nevertheless room for it to enjoy the limited independence from distributive principles that Ripstein envisions.”), but this view is contested. See Kevin A. Kordana & David H. Tabachnick, On Belling the Cat: Rawls and Tort as Corrective Justice, 92 Va. L. Rev. 1279, 1291–92 (2006) [hereinafter Kordana & Tabachnick, Belling the Cat] (interpreting Ripstein as holding the narrow view); Freeman, supra note 8, at 168 (“[For] Ripstein . . . private law ‘has a certain kind of independence’ and should lie outside the basic structure . . . ”). In his newer work, Ripstein side-steps the question. Ripstein, supra note 9, at 291 (“The specifics of Rawls’s formulation need not concern us . . . .”). Murphy holds that the private law is inside the basic structure and that any attempt at narrowing in Rawls’s The Basic Structure as Subject is predicated on a textual mistake. Liam Murphy, Institutions and the Demands of Justice, 27 Phil. & Pub. Affs. 251, 261 & n.30 (1999); Liam Murphy, The Artificial Morality of Private Law: The Persistence of An Illusion, 70 U. Toronto L.J. 453, 457 n.11 (2020) [hereinafter Murphy, Artificial Morality] (“Rawls himself proposed evaluating institutions such as property and contract solely on the basis of social justice as identified by his two principles, which do not obviously have room for values distinctively associated with private ordering.”). Freeman and Scheffler agree that the private law is part of the basic structure. See Scheffler, supra note 8; Freeman, supra note 8; see also Aditi Bagchi, Distributive Injustice and Private Law, 60 Hastings L.J. 105, 109–11 (2008) (discussing the role of distributive justice in contract law).
  12. H.L.A. Hart & A.M. Honoré, Causation in the Law 58 (1959).
  13. Guido Calabresi, Toward A Unified Theory of Torts, 1 J. Tort L. 1, 1 (2007) (“Yes, all that can go out of torts . . .”—referring to causation and the other “hornbook [elements] of liability”—“but tort law won’t cease being.”).
  14. George P. Fletcher, Fairness and Utility in Tort Theory, 85 Harv. L. Rev. 537, 540–43 (1972).
  15. Guido Calabresi, The Costs of Accidents: A Legal and Economic Analysis 70 (1970).
  16. John Rawls, A Theory of Justice 212–13 (2d ed. 1999) [hereinafter Rawls, TJ] (considering the possibility of strict liability).
  17. See, e.g., Richard A. Posner, Economic Analysis of Law 241–45 (9th ed. 2014); A. Mitchell Polinsky & Steven Shavell, Punitive Damages: An Economic Analysis, 111 Harv. L. Rev. 869, 918–20 (1999) (noting defendants should face liability above the harm caused when their gain is socially illicit).
  18. Rawls, JaF, supra note 10, at 12.
  19. Scheffler, supra note 8.
  20. Id. at 217–22.
  21. Id. at 233–34.
  22. Id. at 222.
  23. Id.; Kordana & Tabachnick, Rawls & Contract, supra note 2, at 610 (rejecting the strong distributivism position); Kordana & Tabachnick, Belling the Cat, supra note 11, at 1293 (same).
  24. Kordana & Tabachnick, Rawls & Contract, supra note 2, at 609.
  25. Rawls, TJ, supra note 16, at 61; Rawls, JaF, supra note 10, at 114.
  26. Scheffler, supra note 8, at 222 (emphasis omitted).
  27. Id. at 225.
  28. Id. at 222.
  29. See Rawls, JaF, supra note 10, at 43.
  30. Scheffler, supra note 8, at 222.
  31. Id. at 225.
  32. See id. (“But then, relative to that baseline, the weak distributivist requirement that contract law must not worsen the position of the worst-off is indistinguishable from the strong distributivist requirement that it must maximise the position of the worst off. . . . This means that there is a tendency for weak distributivism to slide in the direction of strong distributivism.”).
  33. Ripstein, supra note 9, at 291, 293–94.
  34. Freeman, supra note 8, at 168.
  35. Gregory C. Keating, Form and Substance in the “Private Law” of Torts, 14 J. Tort L. 45, 56–57 (2021).
  36. Ripstein, supra note 9, at 291.
  37. Id. (claiming that the “specifics of Rawls’s formulation” of the basic structure “need not concern us”).
  38. Id.
  39. Id.
  40. Kordana & Tabachnick, Belling the Cat, supra note 11, at 1288; Scheffler, supra note 8, at 233.
  41. Keating, supra note 35, at 97 (“We cannot understand or justify the law of torts without attending to the interests that it protects. . . . Our law of torts is intimately interwoven with administrative schemes, such as workers’ compensation, and with statutory regimes, such as zoning and direct risk regulation . . . .”).
  42. Id. at 57.
  43. Id. at 97 (“‘Private law’ tort theorists also make too much of form when they present the legal category of tort as its own independent kingdom, walled off from surrounding legal fields.” (emphasis omitted)); id. at 86 (“The tort law of accidents can be wholly displaced by direct risk regulation and ‘social insurance’—as it has been in New Zealand. . . . The vulnerability of our law of torts to such eclipse casts doubt on the thought that tort law is an autonomous realm of ‘private law,’ governed by its own sui generis internal principles.” (emphasis omitted)).
  44. Id. at 57 (“For example, it would be opportunistic and objectionable to use the difference principle to determine the size of damage awards in private lawsuits.”).
  45. Id. at 95.
  46. Id. at 96 (“The mistake would be to think that Rawls’ framework—or some other liberal theory of justice—mandates either ‘private law’ or a New Zealand scheme, or some intermediate arrangement, as a matter of first principles of justice. It does not. To make these choices, we need to supplement basic principles of justice with additional considerations and information.”).
  47. Id. at 97; see also Christopher Heath Wellman & A. John Simmons, Is There a Duty to Obey the Law? 156 n.38 (2005) (noting self-referentially that discussion of Rawlsianism can be “aimed at a Rawls who is more Kantian than Rawls actually wished to be”).
  48. Freeman, supra note 8, at 194.
  49. Id. at 174 (“That Rawls regards the principles of justice as applying to the law of contract . . . is pretty clearly suggested in his discussion of the principle of fairness.”).
  50. Id. at 189 (“Accordingly, unlike Ripstein, I think that more direct engagement with and application of the principles of justice, especially the first principle . . . is suitable for applying Rawls’s theory of justice to the details of a Rawlsian tort theory.”).
  51. Id. at 123 (“There are many social policies for which the difference principle does not appear to be the appropriate standard of assessment . . . [including] ordinary negligence and determinations of fault and remedies in non-economic torts . . . .”).
  52. Id. at 188–89.
  53. Kordana & Tabachnick, Belling the Cat, supra note 11, at 1293.
  54. Samuel Freeman, Illiberal Libertarians: Why Libertarianism Is Not a Liberal View, 30 Phil. & Pub. Affs. 105, 106 (2002).
  55. Freeman, supra note 8, at 123 (“Like determinations of fault and remedies in negligence cases, it would be unfair to require that assets between divorced spouses be divided so as to maximally benefit the least advantaged class . . . .”).
  56. Id. at 184–85.
  57. Calabresi, supra note 15, at 69, 144.
  58. Freeman, supra note 8, at 184.
  59. Kordana & Tabachnick, Rawls & Contract, supra note 2, at 621; Murphy, Artificial Morality, supra note 11, at 457 n.11 (noting Rawls proposed evaluating private law institutions on the basis of his two principles).
  60. Kronman, supra note 1, at 501–05.
  61. Blankfein-Tabachnick & Kordana, supra note 5, at 34.
  62. Rawls, TJ, supra note 16, at 95.
  63. Kordana & Tabachnick, Rawls & Contract, supra note 2, at 621; Murphy, Artificial Morality, supra note 11, at 457 n.11 (noting Rawls’s principles “do not obviously have room for values distinctively associated with private ordering”).
  64. John G. Bennett, Freedom and Enforcement: Comments on Ripstein, 92 Va. L. Rev. 1439, 1440–41 (2006).
  65. Rawls, Political Liberalism 268 (2005) [hereinafter Rawls, PL].
  66. Scheffler, supra note 8, at 221.
  67. Id. at 233.
  68. E.g., Elizabeth Sepper & Deborah Dinner, Sex in Public, 129 Yale L.J. 78 (2019) (discussing the history of public values in the common law).
  69.  David Blankfein-Tabachnick, Maximizing Intellectual Property: Optimality, Synchronicity, and Distributive Justice, 94 St. John’s L. Rev. 1, 51 (2020).
  70. Rawls, TJ, supra note 16, at 95 (“[T]o establish a complete conception of right, . . . parties in the original position are to choose in a definite order not only a conception of justice but also principles to go with each major concept falling under the concept of right.”).
  71. Id. at 303–04 (“I shall not regard promising as a practice which is just by definition . . . There are many variations of promising just as there are of the law of contract. Whether the particular practice . . . is just remains to be determined by the principles of justice.”).
  72. Seana Shiffrin suggests, in a non-Rawlsian context, that contract law may be derived from principles of right rather than solely from principles of justice. Seana Valentine Shiffrin, The Divergence of Contract and Promise, 120 Harv. L. Rev. 708, 716 (2007).
  73. Rawls, TJ, supra note 16, at 95.
  74. Id.
  75. Id. (“[T]he broader notion of rightness as fairness is to be understood as a replacement for existing conceptions.”).
  76. Id. at 93–94.
  77. George Klosko, Political Obligation and the Natural Duties of Justice, 23 Phil. & Pub. Affs. 251, 254 (1994); Wellman & Simmons, supra note 47, at 156 n.38 (“[T]he natural duties actually discussed by Rawls are not ‘natural’ in any very strong sense, but are only the ‘postinstitutional’ moral duties that original position reasoners would select to bind themselves in their subsequent interactions.”).
  78. Rawls, TJ, supra note 16, at 95.
  79. Id. (“[T]he concept of something’s being right is the same as, or better, may be replaced by, the concept of its being in accordance with the principles that in the original position would be acknowledged to apply to things of its kind.”).
  80. Id. at 294 (“[T]he choice of principles for individuals is . . . simplified [since] principles for institutions have already been adopted. The feasible alternatives are . . . narrowed . . . to those that constitute a coherent conception of duty and obligation when taken together with the two principles of justice. . . . [L]et us suppose . . . the choice of the principle of utility . . . as the standard for the acts of individuals. . . . [This] would lead to an incoherent conception of right. The criteria for institutions and individuals do not fit together properly.”).
  81. Id. at 93 (“The important thing is that the various principles are to be adopted in a definite sequence . . . .”); id. (“[T]he principles for the basic structure of society are to be agreed to first, principles for individuals next . . .”).
  82. Id. (“[O]bligations presuppose principles for social forms” and duties for individuals “presuppose such principles . . . .”).
  83. Id. at 95 (“[T]hat principles for institutions are chosen first shows the social nature of the virtue of justice, its intimate connection with social practices . . . .”); id. (“The intuitive idea is this: the concept of something’s being right is the same as, or better, may be replaced by, the concept of its being in accordance with the principles that in the original position would be acknowledged to apply to things of its kind. I do not interpret this concept of right as providing an analysis of the meaning of the term ‘right’ as normally used in moral contexts. It is not meant as an analysis of the concept of right in the traditional sense. Rather, the broader notion of rightness as fairness is to be understood as a replacement for existing conceptions.”).
  84. Murphy, Artificial Morality, supra note 11, at 457 n.11.
  85. Rawls, TJ, supra note 16, at 95–96.
  86. See 26 U.S.C. § 102; Comm’r v. Duberstein, 363 U.S. 278, 287–88 (1960).
  87. Felipe Jimenez, Contracts, Markets, and Justice, 71 U. Toronto L.J. 144, 162 (2021) (discussing optimistically a hypothetical compatibility between distributive principles and the given terms of contract doctrine).
  88. E.g., Zhong Xin Tang, Where the Action Is: Macro and Micro Justice in Contract Law, 83 Mod. L. Rev. 725, 727 (2020) (providing an elegant account of the macro/micro realms and advocating for a compatibility between constraints of reciprocity, notions of justice in transaction, etc.).
  89. Charles Fried, Contract as Promise: A Theory of Contractual Obligation 1 (2d ed. 2015).
  90. John C.P. Goldberg, Introduction: Pragmatism and the New Private Law, 125 Harv. L. Rev. 1640, 1660–61 (2012).
  91. Shiffrin, supra note 72, at 712.
  92. Scheffler, supra note 8, at 224, 232 (discussing possibility the two principles of justice might “threaten . . . the realisation of ‘the important values expressed by free and fair agreements.’”).
  93. Kordana & Tabachnick, Belling the Cat, supra note 11, at 1286–87.
  94. Scheffler, supra note 8, at 232.
  95. Id. at 228–29 (considering the possibility “that the terms of cooperation already mentioned are incomplete. Private law is not to be guided solely by the need to [satisfy the two principles of justice]. There are additional provisions that also have a role to play.”).
  96. Id. at 232.
  97. Rawls, PL, supra note 65, at 266.
  98. Id.
  99. Elizabeth Anderson, The Ethical Limitations of the Market, 6 Econ. & Phil. 179, 182 (1990) (discussing the normative structure of markets).
  100. Scheffler, supra note 8, at 234 (“We may decide that such principles are complete, and that our institutions are to be guided solely by distributive considerations. . . . Alternatively we may decide that they are not complete . . . .”).
  101. John C.P. Goldberg & Benjamin C. Zipursky, Recognizing Wrongs 14 (2020).
  102. Id. at 355 (mentioning “the nature of private rights of action” as a key feature of tort law); id. at 228 (“[P]art of our aim here is to capture lawyerly understandings of the common law of torts.”); id. at 258 (contrasting their approach with that of Dworkin and Posner and stating that they do not “suppose that courts are engaged in the task of crafting optimal rules or making the law the best it can be”).
  103. Id. at 30.
  104. Id. at 353 (noting Rawls is “frequently miscast as exclusively being a theorist of distributive justice” and commenting on the potentially “misleading” nature of characterizing the liberty-oriented first principle of justice as distributive).
  105. Cf. Goldberg, supra note 90, at 1661 & n.110 (arguing that principles of private law need to be accommodated with distributive justice rather than be lexically subordinate to distributive justice).
  106. Freeman, supra note 8, at 107.
  107. Id. at 125 (citing Rawls, JaF, supra note 10, at 64).
  108. Id. at 125, 186.
  109. Id. at 125.
  110. Id.
  111. G.A. Cohen, Incentives, Inequality, and Community, The Tanner Lectures on Human Values 268 (May 21 & 23, 1991) (“I question [the difference principle’s] application in defense of special money incentives to talented people. . . . [T]he idea that an inequality is justified if, through the familiar incentive mechanism, it benefits the badly off is more problematic than Rawlsians suppose . . . .”).
  112. Rawls, TJ, supra note 16, at 131.
  113. Id. at 130–31 (“If there are inequalities in income and wealth, and differences in authority and degrees of responsibility, that work to make everyone better off in comparison with the benchmark of equality, why not permit them? . . . Thus the basic structure should allow these inequalities so long as these improve everyone’s situation, including that of the least advantaged, provided that they are consistent with equal liberty and fair opportunity.”).

On Lenity: What Justice Gorsuch Didn’t Say

Facially neutral doctrines create racially disparate outcomes. Increasingly, legal academia and mainstream commentators recognize that this is by design. The rise of this colorblind racism in Supreme Court jurisprudence parallels the rise of the War on Drugs as a political response to the Civil Rights Movement. But, to date, no member of the Supreme Court has acknowledged the reality of this majestic inequality of the law. Instead, the Court itself has been complicit in upholding facially neutral doctrines when confronted with the racial disparities they create. It advances the systemic racism of colorblindness against any race-conscious remedial legislation, while denying marginalized people relief from unequally burdensome systems so long as those systems’ rationale is facially neutral. This obstinate colorblindness has become so pervasive in the framework of criminal jurisprudence that race is no longer merely the elephant in the room—it is the room itself.

This Essay presents the Court’s recent decision in Wooden v. United States as a case study of what the Court could achieve by saying the quiet part out loud and explaining the white supremacist motives underlying presumptively neutral doctrines. The Court can overturn its misguided doctrines without acknowledging their racial and colonial dimensions, but fixing the underlying rot in the system requires the Court to first acknowledge that the rot exists. Otherwise, new “neutral” doctrines and rationales will continue to crop up to take the place of those that were overturned. The decline of lenity and corresponding shifts in fundamental doctrines can only be fully reversed if the Court is willing to embrace the anti-colonial and abolitionist consequences.

Introduction

“As every civil rights lawyer has reason to know—despite law school indoctrination and belief in the ‘rule of law’—abstract principles lead to legal results that harm [B]lacks and perpetuate their inferior status. Racism provides a basis for a judge to select one available premise rather than another when incompatible claims arise.”1.Derrick Bell, Racial Realism, 24 Conn. L. Rev. 363, 369 (1992).Show More

Derrick Bell

In the second season of Star Trek: Deep Space Nine, the longsuffering engineer Miles O’Brien is arrested and tried in a Cardassian criminal court.2.See Star Trek: Deep Space Nine: Tribunal (Paramount Television June 5, 1994) (depicting the trial of Miles O’Brien on Cardassia Prime).Show More The trial is overseen by an archon, who acts as both judge and prosecutor.3.See id.Show More At the beginning of the trial, she declares, “The offender Miles O’Brien, Human, officer of the Federation’s Starfleet, has been found guilty of aiding and abetting seditious acts against the state. The sentence is death; let the trial begin.”4.Id.Show More As viewers, we recoil from this perversion of justice; it’s the stuff of kangaroo courts. Our notion of justice is grounded in the public perception of a fundamentally fair process.5.See Tracey L. Meanes, Everything Old Is New Again: Fundamental Fairness and the Legitimacy of Criminal Justice, 3 Ohio St. J. Crim. L. 105, 106 (2005) (discussing the role of public perception in the fundamental fairness analysis of due process).Show More We would be shocked to encounter Cardassian procedures in an American courtroom.

And yet, there are two sorts of justice in America. There is the ideal, guided by strong constitutional limits on prosecution meant to produce a fair trial for defendants, even if it means the guilty sometimes go free. Traditional doctrines guide the court to favor the defendant until the prosecution can overcome all reasonable doubt. And then there is the fast and loose world of mass incarceration, replete with plea bargaining, harmless error, qualified immunity, and good faith exceptions. That sort of justice is fit for a colonial power—like the Cardassians—bent on subjugating large portions of its populace. That sort of justice would have little use for lenity. These two systems often exist in parallel, with the latter cloaking itself in the trappings of the former.

In Wooden v. United States,6.Wooden v. United States, 142 S. Ct. 1063 (2022).Show More the Court, in an opinion authored by Justice Kagan, held that a series of burglaries committed at a single address on a single night did not count as more than one “occasion” under the Armed Career Criminal Act’s7.18 U.S.C. § 924(e)(1).Show More (“ACCA”) mandatory minimum sentencing provision.8.Wooden, 142 S. Ct. at 1069.Show More In a concurring opinion joined in part by Justice Sotomayor, Justice Gorsuch indicated that, when interpreting ambiguous statutes such as the ACCA, courts should turn to the rule of lenity before analyzing a statute’s legislative history or purpose.9.Id. at 1081 (Gorsuch, J., concurring).Show More The rule of lenity requires that courts resolve reasonable doubts about the application of penal laws in the defendant’s favor.10 10.Id.Show More

Justice Gorsuch observed that courts have weakened the rule of lenity over time, culminating in the Court’s current interpretation, which requires a finding of a “grievous ambiguity” before courts can apply lenity and find in favor of the defendant.11 11.Id. at 1084.Show More This narrow rule of lenity is one factor that perpetuates mass incarceration and its concomitant racial disparities. But Justice Gorsuch does not say why this shift in the rule of lenity occurred. This Essay presents the narrowing of the historical doctrine of lenity as an offshoot of mass incarceration’s racist roots. That is, lenity—or rather, its narrowing—is one tool courts use to lock up Black, Brown, and poor people, and to keep them locked up.

This constriction of lenity was only an intermediate step in the erosion of constitutional law to permit racially driven mass incarceration. In the early years of the conservative reaction to the Civil Rights Movement, the Court both invented new doctrines and revised or abandoned longstanding ones to police marginalized people and prevent their recourse to the courts. Even the Warren Court contributed to this reaction, giving rights access with one hand while erecting procedural barriers to rights access with the other.12 12.See William J. Stuntz, The Collapse of American Criminal Justice 79–80, 227–30, 260–65 (2011) (demonstrating how the Warren Court’s procedural rulings reduced the focus on a defendant’s guilt in favor of procedural questions, thereby incentivizing the legislative criminalization of increasingly trivial behavior). Daniel Harawa and I will address the racial dimensions of the Warren Court’s ostensibly colorblind criminal procedure jurisprudence in a forthcoming piece, The Warren Court’s Colorblind Counterrevolution.Show More The Court extended harmless error to encompass constitutional violations in 1967.13 13.See Chapman v. California, 386 U.S. 18, 23–24 (1967).Show More The Court invented qualified immunity in 1967,14 14.See Pierson v. Ray, 386 U.S. 547, 555 (1967).Show More then expanded it considerably over the next few decades.15 15.See, e.g., Harlow v. Fitzgerald, 457 U.S. 800, 807 (1982).Show More Police harassment gained fresh justification with the invention of reasonable suspicion in 1968.16 16.See Terry v. Ohio, 392 U.S. 1, 19 (1968).Show More Lenity was (sometimes) corralled to only apply in cases of “grievous” ambiguity in 1974.17 17.See Huddleston v. United States, 415 U.S. 814, 831 (1974).Show More By 1983, the Court began to foreclose the possibility of implying damages as relief for constitutional violations by federal actors.18 18.See Bush v. Lucas, 462 U.S. 367, 390 (1983).Show More The Court created a “good faith” exception to its Fourth Amendment exclusionary rule in 1984.19 19.See United States v. Leon, 468 U.S. 897, 908 (1984).Show More While advancing purportedly race-neutral doctrines, the Court buttressed the racial hierarchies of the carceral state.20 20.See Devon W. Carbado, (E)racing the Fourth Amendment, 100 Mich. L. Rev. 946, 967–68 (2002) (“[T]he Supreme Court’s construction and reification of race in Fourth Amendment cases legitimizes and reproduces racial inequality in the context of policing.”); Brandon Hasbrouck, The Antiracist Constitution, 116 B.U. L. Rev. 87, 116 (2022) (“While the individual mechanisms [of procedural racism] have often been decried for their role in perpetuating white supremacy, the pattern of their adoption and application reveals a much larger problem: the Court is decidedly anti-Black.”).Show More This is what Justice Gorsuch didn’t say. Leaving out this critical context indicates that even when the Court is willing to address the symptoms, it will leave the disease of systemic racism undiagnosed and untreated.

Part I explains lenity and provides a background of Wooden. Part II discusses how courts have shifted and narrowed the doctrine of lenity, so that it almost never applies today. Part III explains the reason for that shift: courts’ narrowing of the rule of lenity is one purportedly race-neutral means of imprisoning Black, Brown, and poor people. Finally, this Essay explains why it is necessary for members of the Court to start saying the quiet part out loud. The Court can overturn its misguided doctrines without acknowledging their racial dimensions. But to fix the rot in the system, the Court must first acknowledge that the rot exists. Otherwise, new “neutral” doctrines will continue to crop up to take the place of those that were overturned.

  1. Derrick Bell, Racial Realism, 24 Conn. L. Rev. 363, 369 (1992).

  2. See Star Trek: Deep Space Nine: Tribunal (Paramount Television June 5, 1994) (depicting the trial of Miles O’Brien on Cardassia Prime).

  3. See id.

  4. Id.

  5. See Tracey L. Meanes, Everything Old Is New Again: Fundamental Fairness and the Legitimacy of Criminal Justice, 3 Ohio St. J. Crim. L. 105, 106 (2005) (discussing the role of public perception in the fundamental fairness analysis of due process).

  6. Wooden v. United States, 142 S. Ct. 1063 (2022).

  7. 18 U.S.C. § 924(e)(1).

  8. Wooden, 142 S. Ct. at 1069.

  9. Id. at 1081 (Gorsuch, J., concurring).

  10. Id.

  11. Id. at 1084.

  12. See William J. Stuntz, The Collapse of American Criminal Justice 79–80, 227–30, 260–65 (2011) (demonstrating how the Warren Court’s procedural rulings reduced the focus on a defendant’s guilt in favor of procedural questions, thereby incentivizing the legislative criminalization of increasingly trivial behavior). Daniel Harawa and I will address the racial dimensions of the Warren Court’s ostensibly colorblind criminal procedure jurisprudence in a forthcoming piece, The Warren Court’s Colorblind Counterrevolution.

  13. See Chapman v. California, 386 U.S. 18, 23–24 (1967).

  14. See Pierson v. Ray, 386 U.S. 547, 555 (1967).

  15. See, e.g., Harlow v. Fitzgerald, 457 U.S. 800, 807 (1982).

  16. See Terry v. Ohio, 392 U.S. 1, 19 (1968).

  17. See Huddleston v. United States, 415 U.S. 814, 831 (1974).

  18. See Bush v. Lucas, 462 U.S. 367, 390 (1983).

  19. See United States v. Leon, 468 U.S. 897, 908 (1984).

  20. See Devon W. Carbado, (E)racing the Fourth Amendment, 100 Mich. L. Rev. 946, 967–68 (2002) (“[T]he Supreme Court’s construction and reification of race in Fourth Amendment cases legitimizes and reproduces racial inequality in the context of policing.”); Brandon Hasbrouck, The Antiracist Constitution, 116 B.U. L. Rev. 87, 116 (2022) (“While the individual mechanisms [of procedural racism] have often been decried for their role in perpetuating white supremacy, the pattern of their adoption and application reveals a much larger problem: the Court is decidedly anti-Black.”).