A Silver Lining to Russia’s Sanctions-Busting Clause?

In 2018, Russia began inserting an unusual clause into euro and dollar sovereign bonds, seemingly designed to circumvent future Western sanctions. The clause worked by letting the government pay in roubles if sanctions cut off access to dollar and euro payment systems. The clause received little scrutiny at the time, perhaps because Russia used a state-owned bank, rather than a global investment bank, as underwriter. But with the invasion of Ukraine and the ensuing sanctions imposed by the United States and other governments, the relevance of the clause has become clear. This Essay examines how the market reacted to the clause before and after the invasion. Our expectation was that the market would charge a premium for bonds with the clause. Investors bought euro and dollar bonds, after all, because they did not want to be paid in roubles. Yet contrary to expectations, investors seemed to prefer bonds that allowed for payment in roubles over bonds that did not. This surprising finding has considerable implications for other countries that may lose access to foreign currency for reasons that are more benign than Russia’s war of aggression. Despite its sordid provenance, Russia’s sanctions-busting clause might turn out to be a positive innovation that could benefit countries facing unexpected crises. Indeed, had Ukraine included such a clause in its bonds, the benefit would have been enormous.

Introduction

After the seizure of Crimea in 2014, the United States and other governments imposed economic sanctions on a range of Russian entities and individuals. Russia’s subsequent invasion of Ukraine in late February 2022 prompted draconian new sanctions, ranging from trade restrictions to a block on the Russian central bank’s ability to access foreign currency reserves.1.For a comprehensive timeline of sanctions imposed against Russia by the United States and other countries, see Chad P. Bown, Russia’s War on Ukraine: A Sanctions Timeline, Peterson Inst. for Int’l Econ., https://www.piie.com/blogs/realtime-economic-issues-watch/russias-war-ukraine-sanctions-timeline [https://perma.cc/MEL7-E7QH].Show More Although unprecedented in scope, it was no surprise that the United States resorted to sanctions to punish a foreign adversary. Countries have long used economic sanctions to achieve foreign policy objectives.2.Benjamin Coates, A Century of Sanctions, Current Events in Historical Perspective, Ohio St. U.: Origins (Dec. 2019), https://origins.osu.edu/article/economic-sanctions-history-trump-global?language_content_entity=en [https://perma.cc/B94U-3X9F].Show More The global dominance of the U.S. payments system, and the dollar’s dominant place among currencies, has made this a tempting practice for the United States.3.See, e.g., America’s Aggressive Use of Sanctions Endangers the Dollar’s Reign, Economist (Jan. 18, 2020), https://www.economist.com/briefing/2020/01/18/americas-aggressive-use-of-sanctions-endangers-the-dollars-reign [https://perma.cc/K2HY-SG4W]; Karen Yeung, How the US Uses the Dollar Payments System to Impose Sanctions on a Global Scale, S. China Morning Post (Aug. 25, 2020), https://www.scmp.com/economy/china-economy/article/3098691/how-us-uses-dollar-payments-system-impose-sanctions-global [https://perma.cc/M5J2-MLXA].Show More Beyond Russia, the U.S. government has used sanctions to target North Korea, Russia, Syria, Venezuela, China, and other countries, as well as institutions and individuals around the world.4.For background on the use of sanctions by the United States, see generally Sheelah Kalhatkar, Will Sanctions Against Russia End the War in Ukraine? New Yorker (Oct. 24, 2022) (documenting the progression of U.S. sanctions against Russia); Nicholas Mulder, The Economic Weapon: The Rise of Sanctions as a Tool of Modern War (2022) (tracing the international development of sanctions through World War II and their shifting scope and purpose).Show More

Foreign states naturally do not relish the prospect of being targeted by sanctions and have looked for ways to eliminate this risk.5.E.g., Frank Tang, China Warned to Prepare For Being Cut Off From US Dollar Payment System as Part of Sanctions Like Russia, S. China Morning Post (June 22, 2020), https://www.scmp.com/economy/china-economy/article/3090119/china-warned-prepare-being-cut-us-dollar-payment-system-part [https://perma.cc/YCC3-AABL]; Karen Brettell, Analysis: As Sanctions “Weaponize” US Dollar, Some Treasury Buyers Could Fall Back, Reuters (Mar. 29, 2022) (describing pressure on foreign governments to diversify their currency use the more the dollar is used as a financial weapon), https://www.reuters.com/business/finance/sanctions-weaponize-us-dollar-some-treasury-buyers-could-fall-back-2022-03-29/ [https://perma.cc/B8A5-HD7U].Show More One option is to reduce reliance on the U.S. dollar, although this requires trade and financial partners willing to deal in other currencies.6.This option inevitably prompts inquiry into whether sanctions might lead to the decline of the dollar as global reserve currency. See, e.g., Michael P. Dooley, David Folkerts-Landau & Peter M. Garber, US Sanctions Reinforce the Dollar’s Dominance (Nat’l Bureau Econ. Rsch., Working Paper No. 29943, 2022), https://www.nber.org/system/files/working_papers/w2994​3/w29943.pdf [https://perma.cc/MGW2-DTU9].Show More More commonly, foreign parties seek ways to bypass or evade U.S. sanctions.7.For a discussion of some of the responses to U.S. financial sanctions, see Pierre-Hugues Verdier, Global Banks on Trial: U.S. Prosecutions and the Remaking of International Finance 109–45 (Oxford Univ. Press 2020).Show More In this Essay, we examine one such strategy, which the Russian Federation adopted after the sanctions prompted by its annexation of Crimea. The Russian government appears to have worried—presciently, as it turns out—that future sanctions would force it to default on its international debt. It sought to prevent this by clever contract drafting.

In 2016, the Russian government was already sanctioned and anticipated that its future conduct might trigger even harsher sanctions. It began to include an “Alternate Payment Currency” (APC) clause in its international bonds—that is, bonds denominated in foreign currency.8.See Lev E. Breydo, Russia’s Bond Roulette, Am. Bar Ass’n (May 20, 2022), https://www.americanbar.org/groups/business_law/publications/blt/2022/06/russia-bond-roulette/ [https://perma.cc/5TEZ-ZGJ9].Show More The clause lets the government pay in an alternative currency if, “for reasons beyond its control,” it cannot pay in the currency specified in the bond. The APC clause first appeared in a U.S. Dollar (USD)-denominated bond and specified alternative currencies over which the Russian government had no control: Euros, Pound sterling, and Swiss francs.9.Prospectus for Russian Federation 4.75% USD bonds due 2026, at 3 (May 26, 2016), https://ise-prodnr-eu-west-1-data-integration.s3-eu-west-1.amazonaws.com/legacy/Prospectu​s+-+Standalone_7cc3442b-cb8c-4394-bc26-33f9ce656e56.pdf [https://perma.cc/YDY6-8A​NP].Show More But, since March 2018, the country’s international bonds have included Russia’s rouble in the list of alternatives. It is the last option; the country must pay in foreign currency if possible. But if not, it can pay in roubles. The meaning of this clause has not been tested in court. At least arguably, the clause lets the Russian government avoid a debt default by paying bondholders in roubles when financial sanctions shut it off from the dollar payment system.

The APC clause is exceptional for multiple reasons. For one thing, we cannot think of other cases in which a country’s sovereign bonds have included an explicit sanctions-busting mechanism. For another, the clause functions as a sort of force majeure clause. In its classic sense, a force majeure clause temporarily excuses a party’s non-performance of its contractual obligations when circumstances outside its control make performance impossible.10 10.Anthony Michael Sabino, The Force Majeure Awakens, N.Y. L.J. (May 16, 2022), https://www.law.com/newyorklawjournal/2022/05/16/the-force-majeure-awakens/ [https://perma.cc/3KBJ-QYRX]. These clauses received considerable attention as a result of the COVID-19 pandemic, since there was considerable debate as to whether the pandemic was a force majeure event. See e.g., Andrew A. Schwartz, Contracts and COVID-19, 73 Stan. L. Rev. 48, 56–58 (2020).Show More But sovereign bonds generally do not include force majeure clauses; the sovereign’s payment obligation is unconditional. In sovereign debt markets, the closest thing to a force majeure clause is the so-called Natural Disaster clause, which allows the issuer to defer payments in the event of a qualifying natural disaster.11 11.Sui-Jim Ho & Stephanie Fontana, Sovereign Debt Evolution: The Natural Disaster Clause, 11 Emerging Mkts. Restructuring J. 5, 5 (2021).Show More Rather than provide for a suspension of payments, the APC clause allows the debtor to use its domestic currency when it cannot access foreign currency.

The formulation of the APC clause as an option to pay in domestic currency has implications beyond the sanctions context. The clause applies to all circumstances where the sovereign cannot access foreign currency for reasons beyond its control. Historically, a loss of such access is a primary reason why sovereigns encounter financial distress.12 12.Barry Eichengreen, Asmaa El-Ganainy, Rui Pedro Esteves & Kris James Mitchener, Public Debt Through the Ages, in Sovereign Debt 7, 33–36 (S. Ali Abbas ed., 2019).Show More The APC clause thus provides a contractual escape hatch from what economists refer to as the problem of “original sin.”13 13.For the classic work on this topic, see Barry Eichengreen, Ricardo Hausmann & Ugo Panizza, The Mystery of Original Sin, in Other People’s Money: Debt Denomination and Financial Instability in Emerging Market Economies (Barry Eichengreen & Ricardo Hausmann eds., 2005); Ricardo Hausmann & Ugo Panizza, Redemption or Abstinence? Original Sin, Currency Mismatches and Counter Cyclical Policies in the New Millennium, 2 J. Globalization & Dev. 1 (2011).Show More A country that cannot borrow abroad in its own currency exposes itself to exchange rate volatility and other risks that can undermine economic stability. High interest rates or weak commodity prices can prompt a debt crisis, which can be avoided if the borrower can temporarily resort to payment in domestic currency. Emerging market borrowers have gradually shifted more of their borrowing into domestic currency, but many have substantial debts denominated in foreign currencies. It may be that Russia, despite causing global chaos and a humanitarian disaster in Ukraine, has inadvertently created a contractual innovation that could benefit other borrowers.

However, the benefit of the APC clause depends on its price. One reason countries borrow in foreign currency is that it is cheaper to do so. A key question, then, is what the pricing implications of using the APC clause have been. How much did the markets charge Russia for the clause? And, once events occurred that brought the clause into play, how did the markets react? In this Essay, we use data on Russian bond prices to analyze these questions.

Our prediction was that the market would charge Russia a premium for using the APC clause. This is because investors who buy international bonds generally do not wish to be repaid in the borrower’s domestic currency, and also because investors might interpret the mere presence of the clause as a signal that Russia anticipated engaging in conduct that would prompt additional sanctions. Conceivably, this premium would not be apparent at the time of issuance. The financial press covered the introduction of the rouble APC clause in 2018, so it could hardly have escaped investors’ notice.14 14.E.g., Jonathan Wheatley, Russia Bond Sales Allow Payments in Alternative Currencies, Fin. Times (Mar. 17, 2018), https://www.ft.com/content/69da000c-2915-11e8-b27e-cc62a39d57a0 [https://perma.cc/UVN8-8Y9J].Show More At the time, however, investors may have been sanguine about the prospect of future sanctions. Certainly, Russia was viewed as a strong creditor, and the bonds were heavily oversubscribed. But during late 2021 and early 2022, the prospect of an invasion of Ukraine became increasingly real. We expected that the market penalty for APC bonds would increase once the invasion (and, thus, additional sanctions) grew increasingly certain.

Markets did not react as we expected. Initially, the market seemed indifferent to the clause, even as Russian forces massed on the Ukrainian border. Once the invasion occurred, the market seemed to wake up to the presence of the APC clause. But rather than charge a premium for APC bonds, as we had expected, the market seemed to value them more highly than comparable bonds without the clause. Although there are dynamics unique to Russian sovereign debt, these findings also suggest that, despite its provenance, the Russian APC clause might be a positive innovation from which other countries facing the risk of unexpected crises could benefit. Indeed, Ukraine itself, which likely faces an unpayable debt burden due to the Russian invasion, would have realized an enormous benefit from such a clause.

I. Background on the APC Clause

The core feature of the APC clause is that it allows the issuer of a dollar or euro bond to pay in roubles if neither the designated currency nor a list of stable alternative currencies is available, and the reason is outside the control of the issuer. As an example, here is the relevant text of the APC clause in a 2019 issuance of dollar bonds by the Russian Federation:

Notwithstanding any other provision in these Conditions, if, for reasons beyond its control, the Russian Federation is unable to make payments of principal or interest (in whole or in part) in respect of the Bonds in U.S. dollars (an “Alternative Payment Currency Event”), the Russian Federation shall make such payments (in whole or in part) in the Alternative Payment Currency on the due date at the Alternative Payment Currency Equivalent of any such U.S. dollar-denominated amount…

….

“Alternative Payment Currency” means Euros, Pound sterling or Swiss francs or, if for reasons beyond its control the Russian Federation is unable to make payments of principal or interest (in whole or in part) in respect of the Bonds in any of these currencies, Russian roubles.15 15.Prospectus for Russian Federation 5.10% USD bonds due 2035, at 66–68 (Mar. 26, 2019), [https://perma.cc/3YBJ-8MYV].Show More

Several aspects of the clause are noteworthy. First, of course, is that it lets the government pay in roubles under circumstances in which, but for the APC clause, it would likely be forced into a payment default. Second, the right to pay in roubles is triggered only if the government cannot pay in a preferred currency “for reasons beyond its control.” The contract does not say when circumstances are outside the Russian government’s control, but the clause is broad enough to cover the types of circumstances that get many emerging markets into trouble (for example, currency outflows that create a liquidity crisis). As events have turned out, Russia has not attempted to invoke the clause, and it is an open question whether the present circumstances are outside its control.16 16.The Russian government has indicated that it intends to pay all of its international bonds in roubles. The Associated Press, Russia Says it Will Pay Foreign Debt in Rubles After U.S. Ban, Associated Press News (May 25, 2022), https://apnews.com/article/russia-ukraine-janet-yellen-government-and-politics-65af86cf89023fbc213c54ab11f212ee [https://perma.cc/29H3-2G54]. This is a default for non-APC bonds and at least a technical default under the APC bonds, since the government has not complied with notice and other procedures applicable to rouble payments. But these are relatively recent developments.Show More Western sanctions are the proximate cause of Russia’s inability to make dollar and euro payments, and Russia cannot directly control the sanctions. But it could presumably entice Western governments to remove them by withdrawing from Ukraine and credibly committing to respect the country’s borders. The question would have to be decided by a court applying English law (the law designated in the contract).

However, it is not a stretch to interpret the APC clause to allow payment in roubles. It does seem that the intent of the clause was to address the scenario in which sanctions cut off access to dollar and euro payment systems. The prospectuses for the APC bond issuances explicitly point to the risk that Western sanctions might jeopardize Russia’s ability to pay in foreign currency.17 17.See Mark Weidemaier & Mitu Gulati, Should Investors Who Care About ESG Buy Russian Sovereign Bonds?, Credit Slips (Mar. 15, 2022), https://www.creditslips.org/credit​slips/2022/03/should-investors-who-care-about-esg-buy-russian-sovereign-bonds.html [https​://perma.cc/EN8T-4JF6].Show More For example, the prospectus for sovereign bonds issued in 2020 details the history of Western sanctions, warns that “continued geopolitical tensions” and new sanctions might put downward pressure on the rouble, and cautions that this might “adversely affect … the Russian Federation’s ability to repay its debt denominated in currencies other than the rouble, including amounts due under the Bonds.”18 18.Prospectus for EUR 750 million 1.125% bonds due 2027, at 17 (Nov. 18, 2020), https://www.creditslips.org/files/nov-2020-prospectus.pdf [https://perma.cc/W6JB-TKRF].Show More Courts generally interpret contracts in a manner consistent with the parties’ presumed intent. This language implies that the intent of the APC clause is to allow payment in roubles when sanctions cut off access to other currencies.19 19.E.g., Guy Faulconbridge & Karin Strohecker, Russia Warns Sovereign Bond Holders That Payments Depend on Sanctions, Reuters (Mar. 6, 2022), https://www.reuters.​com/markets/rates-bonds/russia-says-sovereign-bond-payments-will-depend-sanctions-2022-03-06/ [https://perma.cc/B5T8-4JEY] (noting that the APC was put into bonds in the wake of western sanctions that were imposed as a result of Russia’s Crimean incursion in 2014); Wheatley, supra note 14 (same).Show More Moreover, Gazprom, Russia’s state-owned energy company, also has issued APC bonds. Gazprom has an even better argument for paying in roubles, since its conduct did not prompt the sanctions. We do not think the issue is clear cut for either bond issuer. Bondholder lawsuits probably would be heard by courts in London, and the United Kingdom is one of the sanctioning countries. An English court might be unwilling to let Russian parties continue to pay bondholders in roubles.20 20.For a discussion of this rather unclear basis on which courts across different legal settings periodically invalidate contracts, see Farshad Ghodoosi, The Concept of Public Policy in Law, 94 Neb. L. Rev. 685, 711 (2016); Percy H. Winfield, Public Policy in the English Common Law, 42 Harv. L. Rev. 76, 88, 93 (1928) (discussing differences among judges as to when public policy should void a contract).Show More But it is at least plausible that a court would interpret the clause to allow rouble payments.

So interpreted, the APC clause establishes a mechanism for evading sanctions and, at least potentially, avoiding a payment default. That is a clear benefit to Russia. And while investors who receive rouble payments might worry that the Russian government will manipulate exchange rates or impose capital controls, these are not certainties given the government’s apparent determination to maintain good relations with the market.21 21.The bond contracts are not entirely clear, but they appear to give the Russian government room to manipulate the exchange rate by allowing the NSD, an arm of the Russian government acting as its central securities depository, to determine the exchange rate by reference to the rates quoted by banks in Moscow.Show More

II. Empirical Analysis

We base our analysis on a dataset of sovereign and Gazprom bond issuances as reported on Bloomberg. Overall, we have data on 28 issuances. For simplicity, we focus the empirical analysis on bond pairs, although we have replicated our analysis using bond portfolios. We selected eight bonds with similar maturities to study the impact of the APC clause on the yield spread: two sovereign bonds in roubles, two sovereign bonds in U.S. dollars, two Gazprom bonds in U.S. dollars, and two Gazprom bonds in euros.

Figure 1 shows the daily yield to maturity for the pair of sovereign bonds issued in U.S. dollars.22 22.The pair consists of USD bonds with relatively closely matched maturities: June 23, 2027, for the non-APC bond (“no clause”) and March 21, 2029, for the APC bond (“clause”). Figure 1: Panel A shows the yield to maturity from January 1, 2019, to December 31, 2021; Panel B from January 1, 2022, to September 21, 2022, and Panel C from January 1, 2019, to September 21, 2022.Show More First, we observe a big jump in the yield for both bonds on the date of the Russian invasion (February 24, 2022). Second, from the beginning of 2019 through the date of the invasion, the yield on the two bonds was quite close. On average, over the pre-invasion time period, the yield of the bond with the APC clause is slightly higher than the bond without the clause, but the difference is not statistically significant. After the invasion, the relationship flips and increases considerably in both magnitude and significance. This implies that the market perceived APC bonds as less risky than non-APC bonds. This is the opposite of what we expected.

FIGURE 1. Yield to maturity, percentage, USD sovereign pair.

Panel A. January 1, 2019–December 31, 2021. Panel B. January 1, 2022–September 21, 2022.
                                                                                    Panel C. January 1, 2019–September 21, 2022.

We also analyze pairs of dollar- and euro-denominated Gazprom bonds and observe the same dynamics. Indeed, the pattern is even clearer.23 23.The Gazprom USD pair consists of a non-APC bond maturing March 23, 2027, and an APC bond maturing February 25, 2030. The EUR pair includes a non-APC bond maturing November 17, 2023, and an APC bond maturing April 15, 2025.Show More As shown in Figures 2 and 3, there is basically no pricing difference between APC and non-APC bonds until the invasion. 24 24.Figures 2 and 3: Panel A shows the yield to maturity from January 1, 2019, to December 31, 2021; Panel B from January 1, 2022, to September 21, 2022, and Panel C from January 1, 2019, to September 21, 2022.Show More After that, yields spike for both bonds but dramatically more for the non-APC bond. Again, post-invasion investors seem to view APC bonds as less risky than comparable bonds without the clause.

As a contrast, the pair of sovereign bonds issued in roubles shows little change due to the conflict (Figure 4).25 25.Figure 4: Panel A shows the yield to maturity from January 1, 2019, to December 31, 2021; Panel B from January 1, 2022, to September 21, 2022, and Panel C from January 1, 2019, to September 21, 2022.Show More Neither bond shows an abrupt jump, suggesting that investors with rouble bonds were confident of continuing to get paid even after Russia invaded Ukraine and was subject to severe western sanctions.

FIGURE 2. Yield to maturity, percentage, USD Gazprom pair.

Panel A. January 1, 2019–December 31, 2021. Panel B. January 1, 2022–September 21, 2022.
Panel C. January 1, 2019–September 21, 2022.

Continue reading “A Silver Lining to Russia’s Sanctions-Busting Clause?”

On Rawlsian Contractualism and the Private Law

Introduction: Paradigm Shift and the Rejection of the Conventional View

Shifts in academic paradigms are rare. Still, it was not long ago that the values taken to govern the private law were thought to be distinct from the values governing taxation and transfer. This was thought to be true, although for different reasons, in both philosophical and economic accounts of private law. The question was, for example, whether the law of contract and tort is properly governed by the values of autonomy and corrective justice or by distributive concerns instead. The conventional, indeed, the nearly universal view of Rawlsianism—the overwhelmingly dominant theory of liberalism and distributive justice—was that the private law lies beyond the scope of Rawls’s two principles of justice.1.See, e.g., Bruce A. Ackerman, Social Justice in the Liberal State 195 (1980); David Lyons, Ethics and the Rule of Law 131–32 (1984) (asserting “the principles of justice” “do not apply to private arrangements and transactions”); Anthony T. Kronman, Contract Law and Distributive Justice, 89 Yale L.J. 472, 474, 477 (1980) (noting the “unconcern with the distributive consequences of . . . private arrangements”).Show More

Simply put, for Rawlsianism, the private law was not thought to be the province of distributive concerns. In more academic terms, the private law is not properly understood to be subject to Rawls’s range-limited principles of justice. In this conventional view, the private law is not part of what Rawls describes as “the basic structure of society,” which is roughly limited to basic constitutional liberties and taxation and transfer. This view invites the conclusion that Rawlsian political philosophy—despite its lexically ordered, distributive demand that economic institutions are to be arranged to the maximal benefit of the least well-off—is stunningly neutral with respect to the economic arrangements and ordering of the private law. This thinking led to the conclusion that the private law, if it is to exist, may be justified by values or principles other than Rawls’s lexically ordered principles of justice, whether wealth-maximization, autonomy, or pre-conceived or even pre-political notions of property entitlement.2.Kevin A. Kordana & David H. Tabachnick, Rawls and Contract Law, 73 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 598, 599–600 (2005) [hereinafter Kordana & Tabachnick, Rawls & Contract].Show More

At the same time, the dominant view in law and economics has been that the private law should be sanitized of egalitarian or equity-oriented values.3.Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell, Why the Legal System Is Less Efficient than the Income Tax in Redistributing Income, 23 J. Legal Stud. 667, 667–69 (1994).Show More The seductive idea was that any desired egalitarian moves could be achieved more efficiently through systems of income taxation and transfer than through any egalitarian alterations in private law rules. The conclusion was that the private law should be constructed to maximize wealth (e.g., optimal deterrence in tort), leaving equity-oriented demands for the system of income taxation and transfer.4.Id.Show More The argument’s invited conclusion was that any egalitarian (i.e., non-wealth-maximizing) adjustments to private law rules are inefficient, even if well-intentioned, private law constructions. If one conjoins the conclusions of both arguments, even a Rawlsian arguably ought to adopt the wealth maximizing conception of the private law.

Our early work, arguing against the conventional view, lead to a sustained analysis of this law and economics argument as well.5.David Blankfein-Tabachnick & Kevin A. Kordana, Kaplow and Shavell and the Priority of Income Taxation and Transfer, 69 Hastings L.J. 1 (2017). In outlining what he terms the three most crucial scholarly “caveats” to Kaplow and Shavell’s argument, Guttentag writes,A second caveat to the double-distortion presumption has to do with property rights. . . . Blankfein-Tabachnick and Kordana argue that taking property rights as a given is deeply problematic for the double-distortion presumption because property rights themselves are a creation of the legal system. Moreover, property rights have significant effects on the distribution of income and wealth.Michael D. Guttentag, Law, Taxes, Inequality, and Surplus, 102 B.U. L. Rev. 1329, 1336–37 (2022).Show More We have argued that there is an “entitlement” flaw in both conventional approaches.6.Blankfein-Tabachnick & Kordana, supra note 5, at 8; Kevin A. Kordana & David H. Tabachnick, Taxation, the Private Law, and Distributive Justice, 23 Soc. Phil. & Pol’y 142, 163 (2006) (“Kaplow and Shavell appear to assume the existence of an underlying system of propertyownership and free markets. [The] issue, however, is the very question of the form that property rules should take; that is, we are interested in the question of whether the equity-oriented values that differing theorists hold are best met through tax and transfer, or through (in part) the rules of property law. Thus, it is not clear that Kaplow and Shavell’s discussion, which compares tax and transfer to a tort rule (in isolation) and concludes that tax and transfer is superior in terms of economic efficiency, would (also) apply to the question of the underlying set of property rules.”).Show More Despite well-entrenched views on both sides, our objection has been well-received,7.Kordana & Tabachnick, Rawls & Contract, supra note 2, at 632 (“Our conclusions are bold. . . . [C]ontrary to the conventionally held narrow conception, contract law is within the basic structure . . . [and] the door is open for a deeper understanding of the role that private law plays in Rawlsian political philosophy—it is no longer accurate to believe that Rawlsianism is silent on matters of contract and private ordering . . . .”). Shapiro, for example, notes the similarity between our position in Kordana & Tabachnick, Rawls & Contract, supra note 2, and the recent scholarship, aptly drawing conclusions from the perspective of the new paradigm, taking its baseline as given. Matthew A. Shapiro, Distributing Civil Justice, 109 Geo. L.J. 1473, 1531 (2021). “Rawls’s theory thus does not defuse the conflicts between distributive justice and the liberal state’s other roles so much as deny them, by assigning distributive justice effective, if not formal, priority over other imperatives.” Id. at 1532. He then contrasts the new baseline with that of the former “conventional” view, ably recognizing the conflict within that view, and holding that it is “[o]nly by diluting the requirements of distributive justice” that one might “manage to harmonize them with [backward-looking or deontic] dispute resolution and rights enforcement.” Id. at 1533.Show More and change is upon the legal academy. A wide range of scholars have begun to reject these two conventional views.8.See, e.g., Samuel Scheffler, Distributive Justice, the Basic Structure and the Place of Private Law, H.L.A. Hart Memorial Lecture (May 2014), in 35 Oxford J. Legal Stud. 213, 233 (2015); Samuel Freeman, Liberalism and Distributive Justice 168, 192–93 (2018) (arguing Rawls’s principles apply to the private law); Richard L. Revesz, Regulation and Distribution, 93 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 1489, 1518 (2018) (asserting distributional concerns, not just wealth maximization, should play a broader role in regulation).Show More But in our view, scholars have not always fully recognized what we take to be the full ramifications of the private law being constructed by distributive principles.9.E.g., Arthur Ripstein, Private Wrongs 291 (2016); Freeman, supra note 8, at 185; Zachary Liscow, Note, Reducing Inequality on the Cheap: When Legal Rule Design Should Incorporate Equity as Well as Efficiency, 123 Yale L.J. 2478, 2486–87 (2014).Show More

As we say, academic paradigm shifts are rare; being at the center of one is rarer still. We are honored that the Virginia Law Review has provided us an opportunity to continue the dialogue that proceeds at the heights of the legal academy. In what follows, we aim to discuss our position regarding Rawlsian private law while engaging with scholars who have further developed this complex debate. Ultimately, we hold that, despite the purported complications, there is, as we path-breakingly argue, a Rawlsian account of the private law.

For Rawls, the “basic structure” of society is understood to embody political and legal institutions that materially affect citizens’ life prospects, such as basic constitutional liberties, security of the person, the system of taxation and transfer, schooling, and fiscal policy. These institutions are taken to be subject to and governed by what Rawls famously calls “the two principles of justice.”10 10.John Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement 42–43 (2001) [hereinafter Rawls, JaF] (“The two principles of justice [state] (a) Each person has the same indefeasible claim to a fully adequate scheme of equal basic liberties . . . and (b) Social and economic inequalities are to satisfy two conditions: first, they are to be attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair equality of opportunity; and second, they are to be to the greatest benefit of the least-advantaged members of society (the difference principle).”).Show More However, significant scholarly controversy has arisen over the question of whether the private law (e.g., contract, tort, property, etc.) is properly understood to be within the basic structure of society.11 11.As we noted supra note 1, Bruce Ackerman, David Lyons, and Anthony Kronman held the conventional or narrow view that private law lies outside the basic structure. But cf. Kronman, supra note 1, at 475 (suggesting that Rawls should not have narrowed). Scheffler posits that Ripstein views private law as lying within the basic structure, Scheffler, supra note 8, at 232 (“Suppose we accept that, although private law is part of the basic structure, there is nevertheless room for it to enjoy the limited independence from distributive principles that Ripstein envisions.”), but this view is contested. See Kevin A. Kordana & David H. Tabachnick, On Belling the Cat: Rawls and Tort as Corrective Justice, 92 Va. L. Rev. 1279, 1291–92 (2006) [hereinafter Kordana & Tabachnick, Belling the Cat] (interpreting Ripstein as holding the narrow view); Freeman, supra note 8, at 168 (“[For] Ripstein . . . private law ‘has a certain kind of independence’ and should lie outside the basic structure . . . ”). In his newer work, Ripstein side-steps the question. Ripstein, supra note 9, at 291 (“The specifics of Rawls’s formulation need not concern us . . . .”). Murphy holds that the private law is inside the basic structure and that any attempt at narrowing in Rawls’s The Basic Structure as Subject is predicated on a textual mistake. Liam Murphy, Institutions and the Demands of Justice, 27 Phil. & Pub. Affs. 251, 261 & n.30 (1999); Liam Murphy, The Artificial Morality of Private Law: The Persistence of An Illusion, 70 U. Toronto L.J. 453, 457 n.11 (2020) [hereinafter Murphy, Artificial Morality] (“Rawls himself proposed evaluating institutions such as property and contract solely on the basis of social justice as identified by his two principles, which do not obviously have room for values distinctively associated with private ordering.”). Freeman and Scheffler agree that the private law is part of the basic structure. See Scheffler, supra note 8; Freeman, supra note 8; see also Aditi Bagchi, Distributive Injustice and Private Law, 60 Hastings L.J. 105, 109–11 (2008) (discussing the role of distributive justice in contract law).Show More

The controversy over the question of the breadth of the basic structure is understandable: Rawls is believed to have been less than perfectly consistent. But, with regard to the specific relationship between the private law and the basic structure, we have argued that the historically conventional view—that private law is beyond the reach of the two principles of justice—must be mistaken.

It is important to understand what is at issue in this debate. It is neither a mere scholastic exercise, nor a simple game of words; significant matters of social and economic justice are at stake. Consider, for example, the so-called “causal” requirement in tort law—typically associated with the corrective justice conception. The idea here is that, from the perspective of a consequentialist approach, tort liability ought to be constrained: tort defendants are taken to be liable only for harm they have “caused” plaintiffs and they owe a duty of repair only to such plaintiffs. This “bilateral” or interpersonal relationship, although stated several ways, is central, for example, to backward-looking approaches to tort, even despite the contested status of the concept of causation.12 12.H.L.A. Hart & A.M. Honoré, Causation in the Law 58 (1959).Show More

While the causal requirement may be a necessary condition to a number of conceptions of justice, it can also serve as a significant impediment to otherwise seemingly just “systems” or distributive approaches to accident management.13 13.Guido Calabresi, Toward A Unified Theory of Torts, 1 J. Tort L. 1, 1 (2007) (“Yes, all that can go out of torts . . .”—referring to causation and the other “hornbook [elements] of liability”—“but tort law won’t cease being.”).Show More Consider for example, unjustified risk-taking,14 14.George P. Fletcher, Fairness and Utility in Tort Theory, 85 Harv. L. Rev. 537, 540–43 (1972).Show More whether reckless or negligent. Such activity, absent an actualized harm, is insufficient to incurring tortious liability. So, ex ante accident management systems that focus on liability for unjustified risk imposition are objectionable for failing to satisfy the causal requirement. Still, ex ante liability, properly and narrowly assigned, is an important tool in the social planning and institutional design of accident management. It is useful, for example, in cost spreading and deterrence,15 15.Guido Calabresi, The Costs of Accidents: A Legal and Economic Analysis 70 (1970).Show More both of which can be instrumental to achieving certain accounts of social justice.16 16.John Rawls, A Theory of Justice 212–13 (2d ed. 1999) [hereinafter Rawls, TJ] (considering the possibility of strict liability).Show More

Indeed, our own legal system regulates driving a motor vehicle not only with tort, but also with criminal law. The latter imposes liability for what might be termed risk imposition even in the absence of harm caused—for example, penalties for speeding, driving under the influence, and violating various other traffic laws. If tort law were to be subject to the goals of social planning and distributive justice, say, a special concern for the least well-off or people most likely to bear the cost of accidents, swaths of the causal requirement may need to be jettisoned. In addition to the traffic example, market share liability, where liability is predicated upon plaintiffs’ share of a market in faulty products, as opposed to causation, also might be a common approach to tort liability and accident management. While the imposition of liability in these instances fails to comport with the traditionalist causal requirement, it may be crucial to certain forms of accident management, whether conducive to advancing the position of the poor or creating optimal deterrence with the aim of wealth creation.17 17.See, e.g., Richard A. Posner, Economic Analysis of Law 241–45 (9th ed. 2014); A. Mitchell Polinsky & Steven Shavell, Punitive Damages: An Economic Analysis, 111 Harv. L. Rev. 869, 918–20 (1999) (noting defendants should face liability above the harm caused when their gain is socially illicit).Show More

  1. See, e.g., Bruce A. Ackerman, Social Justice in the Liberal State 195 (1980); David Lyons, Ethics and the Rule of Law 131–32 (1984) (asserting “the principles of justice” “do not apply to private arrangements and transactions”); Anthony T. Kronman, Contract Law and Distributive Justice, 89 Yale L.J. 472, 474, 477 (1980) (noting the “unconcern with the distributive consequences of . . . private arrangements”).
  2. Kevin A. Kordana & David H. Tabachnick, Rawls and Contract Law, 73 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 598, 599–600 (2005) [hereinafter Kordana & Tabachnick, Rawls & Contract].
  3. Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell, Why the Legal System Is Less Efficient than the Income Tax in Redistributing Income, 23 J. Legal Stud. 667, 667–69 (1994).
  4. Id.
  5. David Blankfein-Tabachnick & Kevin A. Kordana, Kaplow and Shavell and the Priority of Income Taxation and Transfer, 69 Hastings L.J. 1 (2017). In outlining what he terms the three most crucial scholarly “caveats” to Kaplow and Shavell’s argument, Guttentag writes,A second caveat to the double-distortion presumption has to do with property rights. . . . Blankfein-Tabachnick and Kordana argue that taking property rights as a given is deeply problematic for the double-distortion presumption because property rights themselves are a creation of the legal system. Moreover, property rights have significant effects on the distribution of income and wealth.Michael D. Guttentag, Law, Taxes, Inequality, and Surplus, 102 B.U. L. Rev. 1329, 1336–37 (2022).
  6. Blankfein-Tabachnick & Kordana, supra note 5, at 8; Kevin A. Kordana & David H. Tabachnick, Taxation, the Private Law, and Distributive Justice, 23 Soc. Phil. & Pol’y 142, 163 (2006) (“Kaplow and Shavell appear to assume the existence of an underlying system of property ownership and free markets. [The] issue, however, is the very question of the form that property rules should take; that is, we are interested in the question of whether the equity-oriented values that differing theorists hold are best met through tax and transfer, or through (in part) the rules of property law. Thus, it is not clear that Kaplow and Shavell’s discussion, which compares tax and transfer to a tort rule (in isolation) and concludes that tax and transfer is superior in terms of economic efficiency, would (also) apply to the question of the underlying set of property rules.”).
  7. Kordana & Tabachnick, Rawls & Contract, supra note 2, at 632 (“Our conclusions are bold. . . . [C]ontrary to the conventionally held narrow conception, contract law is within the basic structure . . . [and] the door is open for a deeper understanding of the role that private law plays in Rawlsian political philosophy—it is no longer accurate to believe that Rawlsianism is silent on matters of contract and private ordering . . . .”). Shapiro, for example, notes the similarity between our position in Kordana & Tabachnick, Rawls & Contract, supra note 2, and the recent scholarship, aptly drawing conclusions from the perspective of the new paradigm, taking its baseline as given. Matthew A. Shapiro, Distributing Civil Justice, 109 Geo. L.J. 1473, 1531 (2021). “Rawls’s theory thus does not defuse the conflicts between distributive justice and the liberal state’s other roles so much as deny them, by assigning distributive justice effective, if not formal, priority over other imperatives.” Id. at 1532. He then contrasts the new baseline with that of the former “conventional” view, ably recognizing the conflict within that view, and holding that it is “[o]nly by diluting the requirements of distributive justice” that one might “manage to harmonize them with [backward-looking or deontic] dispute resolution and rights enforcement.” Id. at 1533.
  8. See, e.g., Samuel Scheffler, Distributive Justice, the Basic Structure and the Place of Private Law, H.L.A. Hart Memorial Lecture (May 2014), in 35 Oxford J. Legal Stud. 213, 233 (2015); Samuel Freeman, Liberalism and Distributive Justice 168, 192–93 (2018) (arguing Rawls’s principles apply to the private law); Richard L. Revesz, Regulation and Distribution, 93 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 1489, 1518 (2018) (asserting distributional concerns, not just wealth maximization, should play a broader role in regulation).
  9. E.g., Arthur Ripstein, Private Wrongs 291 (2016); Freeman, supra note 8, at 185; Zachary Liscow, Note, Reducing Inequality on the Cheap: When Legal Rule Design Should Incorporate Equity as Well as Efficiency, 123 Yale L.J. 2478, 2486–87 (2014).
  10. John Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement 42–43 (2001) [hereinafter Rawls, JaF] (“The two principles of justice [state] (a) Each person has the same indefeasible claim to a fully adequate scheme of equal basic liberties . . . and (b) Social and economic inequalities are to satisfy two conditions: first, they are to be attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair equality of opportunity; and second, they are to be to the greatest benefit of the least-advantaged members of society (the difference principle).”).
  11. As we noted supra note 1, Bruce Ackerman, David Lyons, and Anthony Kronman held the conventional or narrow view that private law lies outside the basic structure. But cf. Kronman, supra note 1, at 475 (suggesting that Rawls should not have narrowed). Scheffler posits that Ripstein views private law as lying within the basic structure, Scheffler, supra note 8, at 232 (“Suppose we accept that, although private law is part of the basic structure, there is nevertheless room for it to enjoy the limited independence from distributive principles that Ripstein envisions.”), but this view is contested. See Kevin A. Kordana & David H. Tabachnick, On Belling the Cat: Rawls and Tort as Corrective Justice, 92 Va. L. Rev. 1279, 1291–92 (2006) [hereinafter Kordana & Tabachnick, Belling the Cat] (interpreting Ripstein as holding the narrow view); Freeman, supra note 8, at 168 (“[For] Ripstein . . . private law ‘has a certain kind of independence’ and should lie outside the basic structure . . . ”). In his newer work, Ripstein side-steps the question. Ripstein, supra note 9, at 291 (“The specifics of Rawls’s formulation need not concern us . . . .”). Murphy holds that the private law is inside the basic structure and that any attempt at narrowing in Rawls’s The Basic Structure as Subject is predicated on a textual mistake. Liam Murphy, Institutions and the Demands of Justice, 27 Phil. & Pub. Affs. 251, 261 & n.30 (1999); Liam Murphy, The Artificial Morality of Private Law: The Persistence of An Illusion, 70 U. Toronto L.J. 453, 457 n.11 (2020) [hereinafter Murphy, Artificial Morality] (“Rawls himself proposed evaluating institutions such as property and contract solely on the basis of social justice as identified by his two principles, which do not obviously have room for values distinctively associated with private ordering.”). Freeman and Scheffler agree that the private law is part of the basic structure. See Scheffler, supra note 8; Freeman, supra note 8; see also Aditi Bagchi, Distributive Injustice and Private Law, 60 Hastings L.J. 105, 109–11 (2008) (discussing the role of distributive justice in contract law).
  12. H.L.A. Hart & A.M. Honoré, Causation in the Law 58 (1959).
  13. Guido Calabresi, Toward A Unified Theory of Torts, 1 J. Tort L. 1, 1 (2007) (“Yes, all that can go out of torts . . .”—referring to causation and the other “hornbook [elements] of liability”—“but tort law won’t cease being.”).
  14. George P. Fletcher, Fairness and Utility in Tort Theory, 85 Harv. L. Rev. 537, 540–43 (1972).
  15. Guido Calabresi, The Costs of Accidents: A Legal and Economic Analysis 70 (1970).
  16. John Rawls, A Theory of Justice 212–13 (2d ed. 1999) [hereinafter Rawls, TJ] (considering the possibility of strict liability).
  17. See, e.g., Richard A. Posner, Economic Analysis of Law 241–45 (9th ed. 2014); A. Mitchell Polinsky & Steven Shavell, Punitive Damages: An Economic Analysis, 111 Harv. L. Rev. 869, 918–20 (1999) (noting defendants should face liability above the harm caused when their gain is socially illicit).

Expedient Imprisonment: How Federal Supervised Release Sentences Violate the Constitution

[T]he Bill of Rights which we guard so jealously and the procedures it guarantees are not to be abrogated merely because a guilty man may escape prosecution or for any other expedient reason.

– Kennedy v. Mendoza-Martinez, 372 U.S. 144, 184 (1963)

Introduction

Each year, more than ten thousand people are imprisoned by federal courts without being charged with a crime, indicted by a grand jury, or found guilty beyond a reasonable doubt by a jury of their peers. Those results are authorized by federal statute, federal rule, and multiple appellate court decisions. The proffered justification: those defendants were convicted of a federal crime and, after serving their full term of imprisonment, failed to comply with a condition of their term of supervised release.

In this Essay, we argue that the federal supervised release system violates the fundamental constitutional protections guaranteed in the Fifth and Sixth Amendments. We begin with a brief history of supervised release, created in 1984 to replace federal parole. Like a defendant granted release on parole, one on supervised release is required to comply with certain conditions set by the court. Unlike parole, where a defendant could be released early from prison in exchange for a promise to abide by those conditions, supervised release does not replace time spent in prison. Best described as post-confinement surveillance, a term of supervised release can take effect only after a defendant has served the entire prison term imposed by a sentencing judge. During that term of supervised release, a defendant accused of failing to comply with any of those conditions may be arrested and sentenced to serve up to five years in federal prison—all without the constitutional protections ordinarily afforded those facing incarceration.

Following an overview of the structure of supervised release, we consider decisions of federal courts, which have repeatedly held that the protections of the Sixth Amendment do not protect defendants serving terms of supervised release and facing imprisonment. We argue that those decisions start from the wrong end of the constitutional analysis by failing to account for the role of the right to indictment enshrined in the Fifth Amendment. More specifically, a defendant accused of violating a condition of supervised release nearly always faces more than a year of imprisonment if convicted—an infamous punishment for purposes of the Fifth Amendment. As a result, we contend that the right to indictment applies to revocation proceedings, and subsequently, the Sixth Amendment rights applicable in a traditional criminal prosecution must also apply. Furthermore, we argue that there is no meaningful distinction, for Sixth Amendment purposes, between a revocation proceeding and an ordinary prosecution, and that decisions concluding otherwise rely on unsupportable legal fictions.

Ultimately, we conclude that the statutory scheme governing supervised release creates an unconstitutional workaround to the fundamental constitutional protections designed to limit the government’s power to arbitrarily imprison. Although dodging the demands of the Fifth and Sixth Amendments surely offers a more expedient route to imprisonment, prosecutors and probation officers should not have the discretion to choose a route to imprisonment that bypasses the Constitution.

I. The History

We begin with an overview of federal parole, the system supervised release was created to replace. We also touch on federal probation, a form of community supervision similar to parole, before turning to the legislative history of the Sentencing Reform Act of 1984 (“SRA”), the statute that created supervised release.1.Sentencing Reform Act of 1984, Pub. L. No. 98-473, tit. II, ch. 2, 98 Stat. 1987 (codified as amended in scattered sections of 18 and 28 U.S.C.); Fiona Doherty, Indeterminate Sentencing Returns: The Invention of Supervised Release, 88 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 958, 996–97 (2013). Professor Doherty’s seminal piece provides a thorough overview of the story of supervised release.Show More

A. Parole

Congress enacted the first parole statute in 1910, modeling the federal system after state parole systems that had been on the books in the majority of states since the late 1800s.2.Id.at 983–84.Show More That statute authorized the early release of federal prisoners who had served at least one third of the prison term imposed by the sentencing judge.3.Id.at 984.Show More The decision whether to grant or deny release on parole was committed to the discretion of a federal parole board,4.Id. at 985;see alsoPeter B. Hoffman, History of the Federal Parole System: Part 1 (1910–1972), 61 Fed. Prob. 23, 27 (1997) (explaining that parole decisions were made by the whole board).Show More and the scope of that discretion was broad: the board could grant parole to any individual who had “observed the rules of [the] institution” in which he was incarcerated so long as release was not “incompatible with the welfare of society.”5.Parole Act, ch. 387, §§ 1, 3, 36 Stat. 819 (1910), repealed by Sentencing Reform Act of 1984, § 212(a)(2).Show More Although allowed to leave prison, a parolee was still considered to be “in the legal custody and under the control of the warden of such prison from which paroled . . . until the expiration of the [prison] term or terms specified in his sentence.”6.Id.§ 3.Show More In other words, a grant of parole allowed a term of incarceration to be served in the community but did not affect the length of that sentence.

A suspected violation of any parole condition could be punished swiftly and summarily: if any member of a board had “reliable information that the offender . . . violated his parole,” the board could issue an arrest warrant and require the parolee to be returned to prison.7.Hoffman, supra note 4, at 28.Show More Only then would the parolee be afforded an opportunity to be heard before the board,8.Id.Show More which could decide either to alter parole conditions or to revoke the grant of parole entirely, sending the parolee back to prison to serve the “remainder of the sentence originally imposed.”9.Id.Show More

In the early days of the federal parole system, courts afforded only limited oversight of the board’s decisions to grant or revoke parole.10 10.E.g., Clark v. Stevens, 291 F.2d 388, 389 (6th Cir. 1961); Hiatt v. Compagna, 178 F.2d 42, 45 (5th Cir. 1949) (“A prisoner sentenced to the penitentiary is turned over by the court to the executive, namely the Attorney General, to have the sentence executed. . . . It is very evident that the whole matter of paroles is left to the informed discretion of the Board. Court action is not made a part of it.”).Show More Federal courts set forth a variety of justifications for declining to overturn the board’s decisions: some concluded that a parolee remained in the formal custody of the executive branch,11 11.Comment, The Parole System, 120 U. Pa. L. Rev. 282, 287–88 (1971); see also Anderson v. Corall, 263 U.S. 193, 196 (1923) (“While on parole the convict is bound to remain in the legal custody and under the control of the warden until the expiration of the term, less allowance, if any, for good conduct. While this is an amelioration of punishment, it is in legal effect imprisonment.”); Padilla v. Lynch, 398 F.2d 481, 482 (9th Cir. 1968) (stating that, because parole is a form of custody, a complaint alleging that the denial of parole violated the equal protection clause is insufficient).Show More while others suggested that parole was an act of grace by a “merciful executive” that could not be demanded as a matter of right.12 12.Comment, supra note 11,at 286–87; cf. Ughbanks v. Armstrong, 208 U.S. 481, 488 (1908) (describing a state’s grant of parole as “the granting of a favor to a convicted criminal confined within one of its prisons”).Show More Finally, some courts rejected constitutional challenges to the parole system by reasoning that the parole board’s relationship with a parolee was not adversarial in nature, given the “genuine identity of interest . . . in the prisoner’s desire to be released and the [b]oard’s policy to grant release as soon as possible.”13 13.Hyser v. Reed, 318 F.2d 225, 237 (D.C. Cir. 1963) (rejecting Sixth Amendment challenge to parole revocation procedures); see also Comment, supra note 11, at 288–89 (stating that the board and the parolee have a shared interest in rehabilitating the parolee).Show More Because the relationship between the parolee and the board was not adversarial, the reasoning went, there was simply no need for courts to intervene to safeguard the rights of the parolee.

In 1972, however, the Supreme Court granted certiorari in Morrissey v. Brewer to consider whether revocation of parole without a hearing violated the constitutional requirements of due process.14 14.408 U.S. 471, 472 (1972).Show More Noting that a parolee was technically still “in custody” and could therefore claim no entitlement to release on parole, lower courts had answered that question in the negative.15 15.Id. at 474–75.Show More The Supreme Court, however, disagreed. Relevant for our purposes, the Court began by explaining that because “the revocation of parole is not part of a criminal prosecution,” the “full panoply” of constitutional protections applicable in a criminal prosecution did not apply to a parole revocation proceeding.16 16.Id. at 480.Show More No real analysis was necessary to reach that conclusion: after all, parole “ar[ose] after the end of the criminal prosecution, including the imposition of sentence”17 17.Id.Show More and involved merely a decision about where the balance of that sentence would be served. Revocation of parole deprived an individual of only the “conditional liberty” granted in connection with early release from prison.18 18.Id.Show More Accordingly, it would make little sense to require the state to initiate a new prosecution simply to require the parolee to serve out the remainder of the existing sentence.19 19.Id.at 483; see alsoJacob Schuman, Supervised Release Is Not Parole, 53 Loy. L.A. L. Rev. 587, 624 (2020).Show More

Although a revocation proceeding differed, for constitutional purposes, from a new prosecution, the Court acknowledged that parole revocation nevertheless inflicted a “grievous loss.”20 20. Morrissey, 408 U.S.at 482.Show More As a result, at least some due process protections were required before parole could be revoked.21 21.Id.Show More Specifically, due process mandated:

(a) written notice of the claimed violations of parole; (b) disclosure to the parolee of evidence against him; (c) opportunity to be heard in person and to present witnesses and documentary evidence; (d) the right to confront and cross-examine adverse witnesses (unless the hearing officer specifically finds good cause for not allowing confrontation); (e) a “neutral and detached” hearing body such as a traditional parole board, members of which need not be judicial officers or lawyers; and (f) a written statement by the factfinders as to the evidence relied on and reasons for revoking parole.22 22.Id.at 489.Show More

Those requirements would eventually be incorporated into Federal Rule of Criminal Procedure 32.1, later made applicable to probation revocation and supervised release proceedings.23 23.Fed. R. Crim. P. 32.1 advisory committee’s note to 1979 and 1989 amendments.Show More

B. Probation

Federal probation has a similar origin story. Although the first federal probation statute was not formally enacted until 1925, federal judges, relying on their broad sentencing discretion, would routinely sentence a defendant to a term of imprisonment and then “suspend[]” execution of that sentence “during the good behavior of the defendant.”24 24.Ex parte United States, 242 U.S. 27, 37 (1916); see also Brent E. Newton, The Story of Federal Probation, 53 Am. Crim. L. Rev. 311, 313 (2016) (noting that federal court judges would suspend prison sentences prior to the passing of the Probation Act).Show More If a defendant failed to comply with restrictions imposed in exchange for granting her leniency in the form of probation, probation could be revoked in favor of imprisonment.25 25.Newton, supra note 24,at 312.Show More As was the case with parole, defendants were afforded little-to-no procedural protections before probation was revoked in favor of prison.

Similar to decisions considering parole revocations, federal courts routinely rejected challenges to the lack of procedural protections available before probation was revoked, on the premise that a grant of probation was a privilege or act of grace afforded by a benevolent court, or suggesting that district courts should have broad discretion over all aspects of probation in order to effectuate the “humane” purpose of probation.26 26.Fiona Doherty, Obey All Laws and Be Good: Probation and the Meaning of Recidivism, 104 Geo. L.J. 291, 330, 335 (2016).Show More

In 1973, shortly after deciding Morrissey, the Supreme Court granted certiorari in Gagnon v. Scarpelli to consider whether “a previously sentenced probationer is entitled to a hearing when his probation is revoked and, if so, whether he is entitled to be represented by appointed counsel at such a hearing.”27 27.411 U.S. 778, 779 (1973).Show More Gagnon, like Morrissey, involved a challenge to a probation revocation that had taken place without a hearing or other procedural protections.28 28.Id.at 780.Show More Citing to a 1967 decision, Mempa v. Rhay, the Court first distinguished a probation revocation hearing from a sentencing proceeding.29 29.Id.at 781.Show More Pursuant to the unique state statutory scheme at issue in Mempa, judges had the authority to defer a sentencing decision in favor of probation; however, if a defendant failed to comply with the conditions of probation, the judge was required to sentence her to the statutory maximum for the original crime of conviction.30 30.Mempa v. Rhay, 389 U.S. 128, 135 (1967).Show More Because that proceeding functioned, in essence, as a sentencing proceeding, the Mempa Court concluded that the Sixth Amendment right to counsel applied.31 31.Id.at 137.Show More

Gagnon, by contrast, involved a different type of revocation proceeding. The petitioner in Gagnon had been formally sentenced to fifteen years’ imprisonment, but the judge had then suspended the sentence in favor a seven-year term of probation.32 32.Gagnon, 411 U.S. at 779.Show More Like revocation of parole, revocation of probation under that scheme merely triggered the execution of the sentence already imposed, and the Gagnon Court therefore concluded that revocation was not a “stage of a criminal prosecution.”33 33.Id.at 782.Show More Further distinguishing the proceeding from a prosecution, the Court noted, was the absence of an adversarial relationship between the state and the defendant. In particular, the state was represented not by a prosecutor, but by a parole officer whose interests were, at least in theory, aligned with those of the probationer.34 34.Id.at 789.Show More Rather than the full panoply of rights afforded in a traditional criminal prosecution, the Court reasoned that only the limited procedural protections identified by the Morrissey Court were required before probation could be revoked.35 35.Id.at 782.Show More

In so holding, the Gagnon Court clarified that whether a revocation proceeding implicates Sixth Amendment rights or merely due process concerns turns on the nature of what the court is deciding. Like in Morrissey, the Court in Gagnon considered a term of imprisonment that had been imposed by a judge but from which the defendant had been granted a reprieve, either in the form of early release from prison or the opportunity to avoid prison altogether. Revocation of that grant of leniency resulted merely in execution of that previously-imposed sentence. Mempa, by contrast, involved something akin to an entirely new sentencing proceeding, to which the Sixth Amendment right to counsel applied.

Probation—and the constitutional mandates set forth in Gagnon—ultimately survived the sweeping changes made by the SRA. Although the SRA directed judges to treat probation as “a form of sentence with conditions rather than as a deferral of imposition or execution of a sentence,”36 36.S. Rep. No. 98-225, at 59 (1983). Arguably, then, Mempa is the only Supreme Court decision that affords constitutional guidance with regard to modern federal probation, which is a sentence in its own right and which requires a judge to engage in a full-blown sentencing proceeding when probation is “revoked.”Show More judges still had broad authority to revoke probation and resentence a defendant for up to the statutory maximum term of imprisonment for the crime of conviction if he or she failed to comply with conditions the judge had imposed in exchange for granting a reprieve from prison.37 37.United States v. Labonte, 520 U.S. 751, 769 (1997) (Breyer, J., dissenting).Show More

C. Supervised Release

By the early 1980s, the federal parole system had come under fire from both sides of the political spectrum as creating unwarranted sentencing disparities among federal offenders and sentences of indeterminate length.38 38.Doherty, supra note 1, at 995.Show More As part of an attempt to comprehensively reform federal sentencing and in response to widespread criticism of parole, the sponsors of the SRA elected to simply abolish federal parole entirely rather than attempt reforms. In lieu of parole, they created supervised release, a form of post-confinement monitoring that followed—rather than replaced—imprisonment.39 39.Sentencing Reform Act of 1984, Pub. L. No. 98-473, tit. II, ch. 2, sec. 212(a)(2), § 3583(a), 98 Stat. 1987, 1999 (codified as amended at 18 U.S.C. § 3583(a)) (“The court, in imposing a sentence to a term of imprisonment for a felony or a misdemeanor, may include as a part of the sentence a requirement that the defendant be placed on a term of supervised release after imprisonment.” (emphasis added)). Imposition of a term of supervised release was required as part of every sentence that imposed imprisonment during the mandatory Sentencing Guidelines era. Since Booker, with few exceptions, imposition of supervised release is discretionary. Nonetheless, it is imposed in the vast majority of federal sentences. SeeChristine S. Scott-Hayward, Shadow Sentencing: The Imposition of Federal Supervised Release, 18 Berkeley J. Crim. L. 180, 186 (2013).Show More As the Senate Report accompanying the SRA explained,

the court, in imposing a term of imprisonment for a felony or a misdemeanor, [may] include as part of the sentence a requirement that the defendant serve a term of supervised release after he has served the term of imprisonment. . . . The term of supervised release would be a separate part of the defendant’s sentence, rather than being the end of the term of imprisonment.40 40.S. Rep. No. 98-225, at 123 (1983) (emphasis added).Show More

As originally designed, supervised release was supposed to afford rehabilitation rather than impose punishment. The punitive portion of a sentence would have been served by the time supervised release commenced, and the primary goal of supervised release was therefore “to ease the defendant’s transition into the community after the service of a long prison term for a particularly serious offense, or to provide rehabilitation . . . .”41 41.Id. at 124.Show More Accordingly, judges were to consider “deterrence and rehabilitation,” but not the need for retribution, in determining whether to sentence a defendant to a term of supervised release and in selecting the conditions to impose.42 42.Doherty, supra note 1, at 998.Show More One important “condition,” however, was mandatory—a judge was required to order that a defendant on supervised release “not commit another Federal, State, or local crime during the term of supervision.”43 43.§ 3583(d), 98 Stat. at 1999.Show More

In line with the rehabilitative purpose of supervised release, the SRA initially provided no mechanism for a judge to “revoke” a term of supervised release. Instead, judges were to “treat a violation of the conditions of supervised release as a criminal contempt.”44 44.Doherty, supra note 1, at 999–1000.Show More In other words, anyone accused of violating a condition of supervised release would be entitled to “trial by jury (for all cases involving a sentence of more than six months), along with all the other procedural protections applicable in a criminal proceeding.”45 45.Id.at 1000.Show More

Just before the SRA went into effect, however, Congress passed the Anti-Drug Abuse Act (“ADAA”) of 1986, a tough-on-crime statute that increased the penalties for certain drug offenses.46 46.Id.Show More Most significantly, the ADAA made what was described as a “technical amendment” to the SRA, authorizing courts to “revoke” a term of supervised release and impose a new term of imprisonment, pursuant to the procedures set forth in Federal Rule of Criminal Procedure 32.1, “if it [found] by a preponderance of the evidence that the person violated a condition of supervised release.”47 47.Id. at 1001; see 18 U.S.C. § 3583(e)(3); Fed. R. Crim. P. 32.1.Show More In so doing, the ADAA jettisoned the carefully crafted procedures originally envisioned by the SRA’s drafters in favor of the revocation mechanism—and limited procedural protections—developed in the context of parole.48 48.Doherty, supra note 1,at 1002.Show More

The sparse legislative history of the revocation provision of the ADAA affords little insight into the intent of its drafters; at best, that history suggests that the amendment was not thoroughly considered.49 49.Id. at 1001.Show More The impact of that amendment, however, was dramatic; passage of the amendment restored a key aspect of the old parole system that the SRA’s drafters had worked so hard to excise from federal sentencing practice.

II. Supervised Release is Constitutionally Different

Citing principally to the similarities between the procedural protections afforded by statute for supervised release revocations and those governing parole revocations, federal courts analyzing the SRA quickly concluded that, at least for constitutional purposes, the two systems were virtually indistinguishable. More specifically, courts reflexively invoked Morrissey and Gagnon to conclude that, like revocation of parole or probation, supervised release violation proceedings were distinguishable from a criminal prosecution to which the protections of the Fifth and Sixth Amendments apply.50 50.Schuman, supra note 19, at 615–16, 615 n.200 (collecting appellate cases).Show More

To be sure, supervised release, parole, and probation share certain similarities—each involves, at one point or another, supervision by a parole or probation officer outside the walls of prison. But we argue that, for constitutional purposes, the differences between parole, probation, and supervised release are more important than their similarities. Most significantly, pursuant to the plain text of the statute governing supervised release, unlike probation or parole, supervised release can take effect only after the full term of imprisonment imposed by a judge has been served and thus cannot afford a reprieve from imprisonment. As a result, when a judge purports to “revoke” 51 51.As United States District Judge Jack Weinstein recognized, even the term “revoke” is a “misnomer” in the context of supervised release. Because supervised release does not replace imprisonment, a judge who “revokes” a term of supervised release is not taking back the freedom she previously bestowed. United States v. Trotter, 321 F. Supp. 3d 337, 346–47 (E.D.N.Y. 2018).Show More a term of supervised release in favor of imprisonment, what she is actually doing is imposing a new and additional term of imprisonment, distinct from the original term of imprisonment imposed as punishment for the underlying crime.52 52.Dissenting in United States v. Haymond, discussed further in Part III, Justice Alito posited that supervised release is equivalent to a sentence of parole:[A] defendant sentenced to x years of imprisonment followed by y years of supervised release is really sentenced to a maximum punishment of x + y years of confinement, with the proviso that any time beyond x years will be excused if the defendant abides by the terms of supervised release.139 S. Ct. 2369, 2390 (2019). But that argument ignores the plain text of the statute, which carefully distinguishes between a term of supervised release and imprisonment. It also ignores the legislative history of the SRA, which makes clear that supervised release was designed to serve a different purpose than imprisonment and was not intended to be interchangeable with imprisonment. Finally, there is no evidence that judges in practice exchange supervised release for imprisonment by imposing shorter prison sentences when they elect to include a term of supervised release as part of a sentence. Empirical evidence instead suggests that many judges routinely impose prison sentences within the range contemplated by the Sentencing Guidelines—which, of course, similarly do not anticipate that shorter prison terms should be imposed where a judge elects to impose a term of supervised release. SeeChristine S. Scott-Hayward, supra note 39, at 186 (2013); U.S. Sentencing Commission Guidelines Manual, ch. 5, introductory cmt., pt. A, sent’g tbl; pt. B, introductory cmt., § 5B1.1 cmt. background (2021).Show More

In our view, that distinction is critically important. Consider the structure of a supervised release revocation proceeding. First, a defendant is formally accused—most often by a United States Attorney or United States Probation Officer—of violating a condition of supervised release. After that formal accusation is lodged with a court, a defendant must either plead guilty to the violation conduct, or instead defend against those accusations at a formal hearing where the government attempts to prove her guilt. If the government succeeds, she faces, in some cases, up to five years in prison for each charge. Because revocation of supervised release involves (1) a formal accusation of wrongdoing, (2) followed by an adversarial proceeding to adjudicate a defendant’s guilt, and (3) leads to a new and additional term of imprisonment, we contend that those proceedings are fundamentally different than those considered by the Morrissey or Gagnon Courts. Instead, supervised release revocation proceedings are—for constitutional purposes—indistinguishable from a criminal prosecution to which the protections embodied in the Fifth and Sixth Amendments always apply.53 53.United States v. Peguero, 34 F.4th 143, 167 (2d Cir. 2022) (Underhill, J., dissenting); see also Rothgery v. Gillespie, 554 U.S. 191, 221–22 (2008) (Thomas, J., dissenting) (discussing elements of a prosecution).Show More

To the extent that courts have considered that argument, they have done so through the lens of the Sixth Amendment. On the premise that a revocation proceeding differs from a prosecution, they have concluded that the full panoply of Sixth Amendment rights does not apply. In our view, those decisions fail to account for the role of the right to indictment guaranteed by the Fifth Amendment. More specifically, in nearly all revocation proceedings, a defendant faces a potential sentence of more than a year of imprisonment if convicted—an “infamous” punishment54 54.Green v. United States, 356 U.S. 165, 183 (1958).Show More within the meaning of the Fifth Amendment. As a result, the right to indictment applies to such proceedings. And if the right to indictment applies, then a revocation proceeding—at which a defendant’s guilt or innocence is adjudicated and that may result in a term of imprisonment—necessarily amounts to a prosecution. In other words, the Sixth Amendment “prosecution” inquiry does not resolve the Fifth Amendment right to indictment issue, but the Fifth Amendment right to indictment inquiry does resolve the Sixth Amendment “prosecution” issue. Furthermore, there are no meaningful differences between “criminal prosecutions” and supervised release violation proceedings for purposes of the Sixth Amendment.

A. The Fifth Amendment

The Fifth Amendment provides that “[n]o person shall be held to answer for a capital, or otherwise infamous crime, unless on a presentment or indictment of a Grand Jury.”55 55.U.S. Const. amend. V.Show More Unlike the Sixth Amendment, which protects the “accused,”56 56.U.S. Const. amend. VI.Show More the Fifth Amendment sweeps more broadly—by its terms, it protects “a person,”57 57.U.S. Const. amend. V.Show More one who has yet to become formally ensnared in the justice system.58 58.Michael J. Zydney Mannheimer, Ripeness of Self-Incrimination Clause Disputes, 95 J. Crim. L. & Criminology 1261, 1321–22 (2005) (noting that the Fifth Amendment protections can apply before a formal prosecution has commenced).Show More Indeed, the right to indictment by a grand jury guards against “an open and public accusation of crime, and from the trouble, expense, and anxiety of a public trial, before . . . probable cause is established.”59 59.Hurtado v. California, 110 U.S. 516, 551–52 (1884) (Harlan, J., dissenting) (cleaned up) (emphasis added).Show More

Significantly, the right to indictment is triggered only when one is “held to answer” for a crime.60 60.U.S. Const. amend. V.Show More Although the historical record on the meaning of that term at the time the Bill of Rights was drafted is relatively sparse,61 61.Elizabeth T. Lear, Is Conviction Irrelevant?, 40 UCLA L. Rev. 1179, 1230 n.246 (1993); Wilkerson v. Whitley, 28 F.3d 498, 502 (5th Cir. 1994).Show More we can conclude at the very least that one is held to answer when he is required to appear and “explain and justify his conduct” in response to the levying of formal charges in a court with the power to punish him.62 62.Ex parte Wall, 107 U.S. 265, 298 (1882); see also Mahon v. Justice, 127 U.S. 700, 713 (1888) (noting that defendant was “held to answer the indictment” after formal charges were served upon him); United States v. McIntosh, 704 F.3d 894, 903–04 (11th Cir. 2013) (quoting Answer, Oxford English Dictionary, http://www.oed.com/view/Entry/8146 (last visited Dec. 21, 2012)) (observing that “answer” means “to speak in reply or opposition to a charge,” a definition recognized when the Fifth Amendment was adopted).Show More

By contrast, the definition of “infamous crime,” as the term is used in the Fifth Amendment, is well-settled. The Supreme Court has explained that infamous punishments include “sentences of imprisonment in a penitentiary and sentences to hard labor. They do not include ordinary misdemeanor sentences of no more than a year in jail.”63 63.United States v. Smith, 982 F.2d 757, 761 (2d Cir. 1992) (cleaned up) (citing, inter alia, Mackin v. United States, 117 U.S. 348 (1886)). Under federal law, persons sentenced to one year or less cannot serve their terms in a penitentiary without their consent. 18 U.S.C. § 4083.Show More Pursuant to federal statute, any sentence of more than one year may be served in a penitentiary. Thus, all federal felonies, i.e., crimes punishable by more than one year in prison, expose the defendant to time in a penitentiary and therefore trigger the right to indictment.64 64.See alsoFed. R. Crim. P. 7(a) (designating that crimes punishable by a term of imprisonment of more than one year must be charged by indictment).Show More

By its terms, therefore, the right to indictment attaches to the great majority of revocation proceedings. First, and most significantly, the statute governing supervised release revocations authorizes judges to impose between two and five years of imprisonment for violating a condition of supervised release, depending on the seriousness of the underlying crime giving rise to the term of supervised release.65 65.18 U.S.C. § 3583(e)(3) (“[A] defendant whose term is revoked under this paragraph may not be required to serve on any such revocation more than 5 years in prison if the offense that resulted in the term of supervised release is a class A felony, more than 3 years in prison if such offense is a class B felony, more than 2 years in prison if such offense is a class C or D felony, or more than one year in any other case.”).Show More In nearly every revocation proceeding, a defendant found guilty of committing the violation conduct could therefore be made to suffer an infamous punishment within the meaning of the Fifth Amendment. Further, one accused of violating a condition of release is formally charged with committing the violation conduct and must appear in court and either admit to the violation or present a defense66 66.See Fed. R. Crim. P. 32.1.Show More—in other words, “held to answer” within the meaning of the Fifth Amendment.67 67.U.S. Const. amend. V.Show More Finally, the Fifth Amendment protects a “person,” rather than an accused.68 68.Id.Show More As a result, even assuming, as some courts have done, that a revocation proceeding cannot be “deemed” a “criminal prosecution” for Sixth Amendment purposes (a proposition with which we disagree, as discussed below), the rights set forth in the Fifth Amendment apply to revocation proceedings.69 69.Indeed, courts already acknowledge that the Due Process clause enshrined in the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments applies to revocation proceedings. See, e.g., United States v. Haymond, 139 S. Ct. 2369, 2391 (2019) (Alito, J., dissenting).Show More

In contrast to the more robust dispute over whether the Sixth Amendment governs revocation proceedings, the role of the Fifth Amendment in revocation proceedings has been largely ignored. Most courts have simply proceeded from the assumption that, because a revocation proceeding is distinguishable from a prosecution, no right to indictment attaches.70 70.E.g., United States v. Peguero, 34 F.4th 143, 157–58 (2d Cir. 2022) (citing exclusively Sixth Amendment cases for the proposition that no right to indictment attaches); United States v. Cordova, 461 F.3d 1184, 1185–90 (10th Cir. 2006) (concluding that there is no Sixth [sic] Amendment right to indictment, and citing Morrissey v. Brewer,408 U.S. 471, 480 (1972)). Although some courts have held that imposing a term of supervised release to follow a prison sentence of less than a year does not transform a misdemeanor conviction into a felony conviction, that does not answer the question whether one facing more than a year of imprisonment upon revocation is entitled to be indicted. See, e.g., United States v. Celestine, 905 F.2d 59, 60–61 (5th Cir. 1990) (per curiam); United States v. Purvis, 940 F.2d 1276, 1280 (9th Cir. 1991).Show More As a general matter, we can imagine two possible reasons why the right would not apply: (1) supervised release violations are not crimes to which the right to indictment attaches; or (2) the indictment (or waiver thereof) supporting the underlying conviction for which the term of supervised release was imposed suffices to meet the Fifth Amendment indictment requirement. We consider both options below.

1. Is an Indictment Required to Charge a Supervised Release Violation?

One possible reason the right to indictment does not apply in revocation proceedings is that violating a condition of supervised release is not a “crime” within the meaning of the Fifth Amendment.71 71.U.S. Const. amend. V.Show More Although there is no clear definition of a “crime” as used in the Fifth Amendment, the Supreme Court has explained that, at the time of framing, a crime was understood to be an “act[] to which the law affixes . . . punishment” or “the wrong upon which the punishment is based.”72 72.Apprendi v. New Jersey, 530 U.S. 466, 510 (2000) (Thomas, J., concurring) (citing 1 Joel Prentiss Bishop, Commentaries on the Law of Criminal Procedure § 80, at 51, § 84, at 53 (2d ed. 1872)); see also Haymond, 139 S. Ct. at 2376 (describing the concept of a “crime” as broad and linked to punishment); Green v. United States,356 U.S. 165, 202 (1958) (Black, J., dissenting) (“How can it possibly be any more of a crime to be convicted of disobeying a statute and sent to jail for three years than to be found guilty of violating a judicial decree forbidding precisely the same conduct and imprisoned for the same term?”).Show More Of particular importance in determining whether a statute creates a “crime” is the measure and type of punishment that the legislature has elected to impose.73 73.Apprendi, 530 U.S. at 501 (Thomas, J., concurring) (observing that a crime “includes every fact that is by law a basis for imposing or increasing punishment (in contrast with a fact that mitigates punishment)”).Show More In fact, it is the nature and severity of a particular punishment that the Supreme Court has repeatedly used to delineate crimes from civil wrongs.74 74.Kennedy v. Mendoza-Martinez, 372 U.S. 144, 167 (1963); see also Hudson v. United States, 522 U.S. 93, 99 (1997) (noting that a court must utilize tools of statutory construction to determine whether a law is sufficiently punitive to transform a civil remedy into a criminal penalty).Show More

Consider that definition in the context of a revocation proceeding. To be sure, Section 3583 is not a traditional criminal statute—for example, it does not identify the elements comprising a particular offense for which punishment can or must be imposed. By its terms, however, Section 3583 does “affix[] punishment”75 75.Apprendi, 530 U.S. at 510 (Thomas, J., concurring) (cleaned up) (citing 1 Joel Prentiss Bishop, Commentaries on the Law of Criminal Procedure § 80, 51 (2d ed. 1872)).Show More to the act of violating a condition of supervised release.76 76.18 U.S.C. § 3583(e).Show More Most importantly, the nature and severity of that punishment—incarceration in a federal prison or penitentiary—is indistinguishable from the punishment imposed for committing a felony.77 77.See, e.g., Mendoza-Martinez, 372 U.S. at 167 (“[F]orfeiture of citizenship is a penalty for the act of leaving or staying outside the country to avoid the draft. This being so, the Fifth and Sixth Amendments mandate that this punishment cannot be imposed without a prior criminal trial and all its incidents, including indictment, notice, confrontation, jury trial, assistance of counsel, and compulsory process for obtaining witnesses. If the sanction these sections impose is punishment, and it plainly is, the procedural safeguards required as incidents of a criminal prosecution are lacking.”).Show More As a result, the right to indictment ought to attach.

2. Can the Indictment Supporting the Underlying Conviction Also Support a Charge of Violating Supervised Release?

A second possibility is that every person serving a term of supervised release for a felony conviction has already been indicted—or waived the right to indictment—in connection with the original prosecution. It is therefore at least theoretically possible that the indictment for that original offense could satisfy the right to indictment for any supervised release violation. After all, some courts (again relying on Morrissey) have held that any new term of imprisonment imposed following supervised release revocation is authorized by the original sentence and, by implication, the original indictment.78 78.See infra Part III.A (discussing the “original penalty” rationale). That rationale overlooks the statutes respectively authorizing a sentence of probation and a sentence of imprisonment. Compare 18 U.S.C. § 3564(e) (“A sentence of probation remains conditional and subject to revocation until its expiration or termination.” (emphasis ours)), with id. § 3582(b) (“Notwithstanding the fact that a sentence to imprisonment can subsequently be [modified due to compassionate release or corrected or appealed,] a judgment of conviction that includes such a sentence [of imprisonment] constitutes a final judgment for all other purposes.”) and id. § 3582(c) (instructing that with rare exceptions, a “court may not modify a term of imprisonment once it has been imposed”).Show More

Of course, it would be metaphysically impossible for an indictment for the underlying conviction to have actually included charges relating to yet-to-be-committed violation conduct. In addition, the idea that the original conviction somehow authorizes any new punishment imposed after revocation is foreclosed by Supreme Court precedent. Specifically, the Supreme Court has repeatedly held that an indictment must charge the elements of the crime for which an individual is ultimately prosecuted and punished. Indeed,

[t]he very purpose of the requirement that a man be indicted by grand jury is to limit his jeopardy to offenses charged by a group of his fellow citizens acting independently of either prosecuting attorney or judge. Thus the basic protection the grand jury was designed to afford is defeated by a device or method which subjects the defendant to prosecution for interference with [conduct] which the grand jury did not charge.79 79.Stirone v. United States, 361 U.S. 212, 218 (1960).Show More

Any substantive charges set forth in that indictment “may not be broadened through amendment except by the grand jury itself.”80 80.Id. at 215–16; United States v. Simmons, 11 F.4th 239, 268 (4th Cir. 2021) (“[I]ncongruity between the indictment and the conviction that a constructive amendment causes destroys the defendant’s substantial right to be tried only on charges presented in the indictment.” (cleaned up) (quoting Stirone, 361 U.S. at 217)).Show More As a result, the original indictment cannot constitutionally cover future conduct unknown to the grand jury at the time it voted to indict.81 81.Some decisions hold that, when an indictment fails to charge one of the elements of a charged offense, but there is overwhelming evidence in support of the missing element, the right to indictment is not violated. E.g., United States v. Nkansah, 699 F.3d 743, 752 (2d Cir. 2012) (citing United States v. Cotton, 535 U.S. 625, 633 (2002)). Of course, supervised release violation conduct is not an element of any offense actually charged in the underlying indictment, but instead entirely new and separate conduct that can occur years (or even decades) after the original indictment.Show More

The constitutional guarantee against double jeopardy also forecloses the argument that the original indictment somehow covers the new punishment. The Double Jeopardy Clause protects not only against multiple prosecutions for the same offense, but also “against multiple punishments for the same offense”82 82.North Carolina v. Pearce, 395 U.S. 711, 717 (1969), overruled on other grounds byAlabama v. Smith, 490 U.S. 794, 798 (1989); see also Ex parte Lange, 85 U.S. 163, 173 (1873) (“[T]he Constitution was designed as much to prevent the criminal from being twice punished for the same offence as from being twice tried for it.”).Show More unless cumulative punishments are specifically authorized by the legislature.83 83.Missouri v. Hunter, 459 U.S. 359, 368–69 (1983) (Marshall, J., dissenting) (“Where, as here, a legislature specifically authorizes cumulative punishment under two statutes . . . the prosecutor may seek and the trial court or jury may impose cumulative punishment under such statutes in a single trial.”).Show More Given that post-revocation penalties are not imposed as part of the original prosecution, any attempt to attribute those penalties to the original conviction runs afoul of the constitutional prohibition against multiple punishments for the same offense.84 84.In the Sentencing Reform Act, Congress “forbade the federal courts from ‘modify[ing] a term of imprisonment once it has been imposed.’” United States v. Jones, 980 F.3d 1098, 1103–04 (6th Cir. 2020) (quoting Sentencing Reform Act of 1984, Pub. L. No. 98–473, tit. II, ch. 2, § 212(a), 98 Stat. 1987, 1998). To avoid constitutional problems, when courts are authorized to modify sentences, they are limited to reducing sentences. See18 U.S.C. § 3582(c).Show More

In sum, the punishment imposed for violating a condition of supervised release cannot be based on the original prosecution—either the original conviction or the original sentence. As a result, courts cannot constitutionally imprison a person for violating a condition of supervised release unless she has been indicted for that conduct by a grand jury.

B. The Sixth Amendment

The Sixth Amendment proclaims that,

[i]n all criminal prosecutions, the accused shall enjoy the right to a speedy and public trial, by an impartial jury . . . [;] to be informed of the nature and cause of the accusation; to be confronted with the witnesses against him; to have compulsory process for obtaining witnesses in his favor, and to have the Assistance of Counsel for his defence.85 85.U.S. Const. amend. VI.Show More

In our view, whether or not the Sixth Amendment applies in revocation proceedings is a question with a straightforward answer—because the right to indictment must apply in revocation proceedings, revocation proceedings necessarily constitute prosecutions. The indictment, in other words, transforms a “person” into “the accused.”86 86.Although the right to a speedy trial may attach before an indictment issues, each of the rights encompassed in the Sixth Amendment attaches by the time an indictment is returned. See United States v. Black, 918 F.3d 243, 256 (2d Cir. 2019).Show More

But even putting aside the implications of the right to indictment, revocation proceedings have all the earmarks of a traditional prosecution within the meaning of the Sixth Amendment. Although historical records do not offer a precise definition of the term “prosecution” at the time the Sixth Amendment was adopted,87 87.See, e.g., Rothgery v. Gillespie County, 554 U.S. 191, 219 (2008) (Thomas, J., dissenting) (citing to 4 William Blackstone, Commentaries *289, to discern the Framers’ intent); see alsoSanjay Chhablani, Disentangling the Sixth Amendment, 11 U. Pa. J. Const. L. 487, 492 (2009) (noting the dearth of early Supreme Court opinions shedding light on the scope of Sixth Amendment protections).Show More we can glean from that record the type of proceedings to which the rights encompassed in the Sixth Amendment were designed to apply and the interests they were designed to safeguard.

First, the Sixth Amendment is distinct from the Fifth in that it protects only “the accused.”88 88.U.S. Const. amend. VI.Show More A prosecution, within the meaning of the Sixth Amendment, necessarily involves the “filing [of] formal charges in a court with jurisdiction to try and punish the defendant.”89 89.Rothgery, 554 U.S. at 223 (Thomas, J., dissenting); see alsoUnited States v. Haymond, 139 S. Ct. 2369, 2376 (2019) (plurality opinion) (describing a prosecution as “the process of exhibiting formal charges against an offender before a legal tribunal” (cleaned up) (quoting Noah Webster, An American Dictionary of the English Language (1st ed. 1828))).Show More The filing of a formal accusation transforms the proceeding into an adversarial one, with the government standing on one side of the courtroom as the accuser and the citizen standing on the other as the accused. That adversarial relationship between citizen and government is a “defining characteristic”90 90.Rothgery, 554 U.S. at 234 (Thomas, J., dissenting).Show More of a prosecution; perhaps above all else, the Sixth Amendment was designed to protect a citizen “faced with the prosecutorial forces of organized society.”91 91.Id. at 198(quoting Kirby v. Illinois, 406 U.S. 682, 689 (1972)); see also Middendorf v. Henry, 425 U.S. 25, 40 (1976) (“Yet the adversary nature of civilian criminal proceedings is one of the touchstones of the Sixth Amendment’s right to counsel.”); Williams v. Florida, 399 U.S. 78, 112 (1970) (Black, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part) (noting that the Fifth and Sixth Amendments were designed “to shield the defendant against state power”).Show More And perhaps most importantly, a prosecution is a proceeding that can result in the infliction of punishment—most significantly, the loss of liberty.92 92.Note, An Argument for Confrontation under the Federal Sentencing Guidelines, 105 Harv. L. Rev. 1880, 1889 (1992) (arguing that the Sixth Amendment was “meant to apply” when “the state decides how to punish an individual for criminal behavior”); 4 William Blackstone, Commentaries *301 (defining a prosecution in part as “the next step towards the punishment of offenders”); Search for Collocate “Punish” Within Four Words of “Prosecute”, Brigham Young University’s Corpus of Founding Era American English, Version 6.1.0, https://lawcorp​us.byu.edu/byucoeme/concordances (last visited Oct. 17, 2022) (thirteen hits) (enter query term “prosecute” in main search bar; then enter “punish” under the “collocates” tab below, with “scope left” and “scope right” set to four; then click “apply changes”).Show More

In our view, a supervised release revocation proceeding has all the “defining characteristics”93 93.Rothgery, 554 U.S. at 234 (Thomas, J., dissenting).Show More of a prosecution within the meaning of the Sixth Amendment. First, one accused of violating a condition of supervised release is formally accused of committing new, wrongful conduct in a court with the power to adjudicate guilt or innocence and impose punishment. Most significantly—and unlike the petitioners in Morrissey and Gagnon—a defendant convicted of violation conduct may be sentenced to a new and additional punishment, distinct from any punishment inflicted for the original offense. As a result, one facing revocation of supervised release is, for Sixth Amendment purposes, an “accused”94 94.U.S. Const. amend. VI.Show More—she has been formally charged with committing an act to which the law “affixes punishment” in the form of an additional prison sentence.95 95.United States v. Haymond, 139 S. Ct. 2369, 2376 (2019) (plurality opinion) (cleaned up); see also id.at 2392 (defining the accused as “an individual ‘[c]harged with a crime, by a legal process’”) (Alito, J., dissenting) (quoting Noah Webster, An American Dictionary of the English Language (1828)). Dissenting in Haymond, Justice Alito argued that one serving a term of supervised release is no longer the “accused,” but has instead been properly convicted of the underlying offense, and that any sanctions imposed for violation conduct merely sanction a breach of the court’s trust. Id.at 2392–93. As a result, he argued, the Sixth Amendment was inapplicable. Id. at 2392.But as Justice Alito also recognized, the original prosecution has ended by the time a revocation proceeding begins. Id.at 2393–95. And as discussed further below, there is no statutory support for the idea that revocation sanctions a defendant’s breach of the court’s trust. Instead, revocation can only reasonably be understood to sanction the new offense conduct—meaning one charged with a supervised release violation stands in the shoes of the “accused,” for Sixth Amendment purposes. And although the underlying criminal conviction may certainly deprive one of certain constitutional rights, the right to be indicted and the right to trial by jury for a new prosecution are not among them. Cf. Strunk v. United States, 412 U.S. 434, 437–38 (1973) (acknowledging that defendant had the right to a speedy trial irrespective of the fact that he was incarcerated in a penitentiary on an unrelated charge). As a result, the mere fact that a releasee stands convicted of the crime giving rise to the term of supervised release does not afford the government the right to deprive her of Fifth and Sixth Amendment rights in a new prosecution.Show More Finally, the proceeding convened to adjudicate her guilt—a revocation hearing—is inherently adversarial in nature. Although revocation proceedings may be initiated by a U.S. Probation Officer, a U.S. Attorney, or even the court itself, it is an Assistant U.S. Attorney, with all of the resources made available for prosecuting federal crimes, who generally takes on the burden of proving guilt by a preponderance of the evidence. And at that proceeding, the government—whether represented by a U.S. Probation Officer or a U.S. Attorney—has undoubtedly “committed itself to prosecute” such that “the adverse positions of government and defendant have solidified.”96 96.Rothgery, 554 U.S. at 233 (Thomas, J., dissenting) (quoting Kirby v. Illinois, 406 U.S. 682, 689 (1972)).Show More In other words, for Sixth Amendment purposes, the proceeding is indistinguishable from a traditional prosecution.

III. The Constitutional Work Arounds

Unlike with the right to indictment, courts have repeatedly wrestled with the question of whether the Sixth Amendment rights applicable to a traditional criminal prosecution govern supervised release revocation proceedings and have uniformly held that they do not. We consider the primary arguments advanced by those courts below.

A. Part of the Original Penalty

Shortly after enactment of the ADAA, Congress amended Section 3583 to make it more punitive. Specifically, amendments enacted in 1987 had the effect of increasing the length of the supervised release term a court could impose, and, more importantly, the length of imprisonment a defendant could serve upon revocation.97 97.Doherty, supra note 1, at 1003.Show More Amendments passed in 1994 required “revocation” and imprisonment if a court found by a preponderance of the evidence that a supervisee had violated certain “conditions” of supervised release.98 98.Id. at 1003–04.Show More

Defendants sentenced pursuant to those amendments quickly began raising ex post facto challenges, forcing appellate courts to grapple, for the first time, with what post-revocation penalties were actually punishing.99 99.Id. at 1004.Show More Relying in part on the absence of constitutional protections prescribed by Section 3583(e) before supervised release could be revoked, a majority of appellate courts concluded that post-revocation imprisonment had to be part of the original penalty for the underlying crime.100 100.Id. at 1006–07.Show More In so holding, those courts acknowledged that the alternative interpretation—that the new prison term was punishing the violation conduct itself—was constitutionally problematic. In particular, if that new prison term was punishment for the new conduct, courts were imprisoning people for conduct that often did not constitute a crime and were doing so without any of the procedural protections available in an ordinary prosecution.101 101.E.g., United States v. Beals, 87 F.3d 854, 859 (7th Cir. 1996) (concluding that revocation had to sanction the original offense because “[c]onduct that violates the terms of supervised release, like that of parole violations, is often not criminal”); United States v. Meeks, 25 F.3d 1117, 1123 (2d Cir. 1994) (relying in part on the lack of “fundamental constitutional procedural protections” in a revocation proceeding to conclude that it must be punishing the original offense).Show More

The question reached the Supreme Court in Johnson v. United States, a case involving yet another ex post facto challenge to the application of a particular amendment to Section 3583.102 102.Specifically, Johnson concerned a challenge to the application of § 3583(h), which authorized a district court to (1) revoke a term of supervised release; (2) impose a term of imprisonment; and (3) impose a new term of supervised release to follow imprisonment. 529 U.S. 694, 696 (2000).Show More Although acknowledging the “intuitive appeal” 103 103.Id. at 700.Show More of the idea that revocation sanctioned the violation conduct itself, the Johnson Court candidly explained that “construing revocation and reimprisonment as punishment for the violation of the conditions of supervised release” would essentially render the statute unconstitutional.104 104.Id.Show More More specifically, if the new term of imprisonment was sanctioning the new conduct, there were at least three major constitutional issues: (1) courts were imprisoning people for conduct that was not criminal; (2) courts were imprisoning people based on a finding by a single judge employing a preponderance of the evidence standard; and (3) where the violation conduct was criminal in its own right, courts were punishing people twice—potentially in violation of the Double Jeopardy Clause.105 105.Id. The double-jeopardy problem the Court identified in Johnson involved punishing violation conduct both as a supervised release violation and as the basis for a new prosecution. The Court did not consider the double-jeopardy problems discussed above—the fact that the imposition of an additional penalty for the original crime also violates the Double Jeopardy Clause.Show More In short, if post-revocation penalties were attributable to the new offense conduct, revocation proceedings looked uncomfortably similar to criminal prosecutions, albeit without affording defendants the requisite constitutional protections.106 106.Johnson did not make that point explicitly; it did, however, cite to Gagnon to suggest that revocation was not akin to a prosecution. Id. at 700–01.Show More Rather than address those constitutional problems, the Johnson Court offered a workaround—by calling the new prison term “part of the penalty for the initial offense,” the Court suggested those constitutional problems could simply be “avoid[ed].”107 107.Id. at 700.Show More

Ultimately, the Johnson Court also dodged the question whether the application of amendments to Section 3583 violated the Ex Post Facto Clause, rendering its discussion of the constitutionality of post-revocation penalties dicta that might reasonably have been disregarded.108 108.Id.at 713; see also Jacob Schuman, Criminal Violations, 108 Va. L. Rev. (forthcoming Dec. 2022) (manuscript at 125) (on file with authors) (noting the Court’s evasion of that constitutional obstacle and its adoption of the “original offense” doctrine could be seen as dicta).Show More Instead, and perhaps because of the dearth of other Supreme Court authority addressed to supervised release, lower courts seized upon that rationale in response to myriad challenges to the constitutionality of Section 3583. Claiming that post-revocation penalties could be “treated” or “deemed” part of the original penalty—rather than new punishment for new conduct—courts purported to distinguish revocation proceedings from prosecutions. As a result, they determined that defendants in those proceedings were not entitled to “the full panoply of rights that criminal defendants generally enjoy.”109 109.United States v. Peguero, 34 F.4th 143, 160 (2d Cir. 2022); see also United States v. Jackson, 559 F.3d 368, 371 (5th Cir. 2009) (“Post-revocation sanctions are not a separate penalty for purposes of the Double Jeopardy clause—they are part of the penalty for the original offense.”); United States v. Gavilanes-Ocaranza, 772 F.3d 624, 627 (9th Cir. 2014) (“The revocation of supervised release is not a criminal prosecution for Sixth Amendment purposes, because the violation ‘simply triggers the execution of the conditions of the original sentence.’” (quoting United States v. Paskow, 11 F.3d 873, 881 (9th Cir. 1993))); United States v. Doka, 955 F.3d 290, 294 (2d Cir. 2020) (noting defendants in supervised release proceedings are not entitled to holding the government to a burden of proof beyond a reasonable doubt or to a trial by jury).Show More

B. Conditional Liberty

The second argument invoked to reject Sixth Amendment challenges to revocation proceedings developed in response to Apprendi v. New Jersey, a Supreme Court decision issued in 2000.110 110.530 U.S. 466 (2000).Show More Apprendi considered the difference between a sentencing factor and an element of a crime for Sixth Amendment purposes and involved a state sentencing scheme that blurred the lines between the two. Building on its prior precedents, the Apprendi Court drew a bright line rule. “Other than the fact of a prior conviction,” the Court explained, “any fact that increases the penalty for a crime beyond the prescribed statutory maximum must be submitted to a jury, and proved beyond a reasonable doubt.”111 111.Id. at 490.Show More

In the wake of Apprendi and its progeny,112 112.The Supreme Court followed up Apprendiwith Blakely v. Washington, in which it clarified that “‘the statutory maximum’ for Apprendi purposes is the maximum sentence a judge may impose solely on the basis of the facts reflected in the jury verdict or admitted by the defendant.” 542 U.S. 296, 303 (2004) (emphasis omitted). Relying in part on that holding, the Court then decided United States v. Booker, in which it held that § 3553(b), which made the Guidelines mandatory and binding on district courts, was unconstitutional. 543 U.S. 220, 245 (2005).Show More defendants began to argue that, if the sanctions for violations of supervised release exceeded the statutory maximum for the underlying offense, the revocation sentence amounted to a violation of Apprendi.113 113.E.g., United States v. McIntosh, 630 F.3d 699, 702–03 (7th Cir. 2011);see also United States v. Huerta-Pimental, 445 F.3d 1220, 1222–25 (9th Cir. 2006) (holding Apprendi has no effect on the imposition of supervised release under § 3583);United States v. Work, 409 F.3d 484, 489–92 (1st Cir. 2005) (rejecting the defendant’s argument that the inclusion of a term of supervised release as a part of his original sentence exposed him to additional punishment beyond the statutory maximum).Show More Others raised more sweeping challenges to the statutory scheme, claiming that imposing a term of imprisonment based solely on a single judge’s findings—made by a preponderance of the evidence—violated the Fifth and Sixth Amendments.114 114.United States v. Cunningham, 607 F.3d 1264, 1266–67 (11th Cir. 2010); United States v. Carlton, 442 F.3d 802, 807 (2d Cir. 2006).Show More

Perhaps because the “original penalty” rationale seemed to run headlong into the holding of Apprendi and its progeny, appellate courts confronting Apprendi-based challenges to revocation fell back on Morrissey, which, of course, is a decision about parole. In particular, courts invoked Morrissey’s discussion of “conditional liberty” to justify revoking supervised release without affording a defendant’s Sixth Amendment rights. One Second Circuit case—United States v. Carlton—offers the strongest example. The petitioner in Carlton, sentenced by a district court to serve thirty-five months’ imprisonment for committing armed bank robbery while on supervised release, challenged his revocation sentence as violative of the Fifth and Sixth Amendments.115 115.442 F.3d at 807.Show More Recognizing that simply labeling that new punishment part of the original penalty did not satisfactorily resolve the Sixth Amendment problem, the Carlton court advanced a new theory. Reasoning that a defendant on supervised release—like one on parole—enjoys only a pared down version of liberty, the Carlton court explained that the petitioner was not entitled to the full complement of rights afforded one “to whom the presumption of innocence attaches.”116 116.Id. at 809.Show More In other words, by virtue of the fact that he had been convicted of a crime and sentenced to a term of supervised release, the petitioner had “surrender[ed] . . . certain constitutional rights” such as his “rights to trial by jury and to having accusations against him proved beyond a reasonable doubt.”117 117.Id. at 809–10.Show More In the wake of Carlton, other courts rejected challenges to the revocation scheme premised on Apprendi by invoking similar reasoning (and often by citing to Carlton).118 118.E.g., Cunningham, 607 F.3d at 1267–68.Show More

C. Breach of Trust

Finally, courts have deemed the Sixth Amendment inapplicable in revocation proceedings by concluding that post-revocation penalties merely sanction a defendant’s “breach of trust” rather than punish the violation conduct itself. Citing principally to the Sentencing Commission’s policy statement on supervision violations,119 119.U.S. Sent’g Guidelines Manual ch. 7, pt. A, introductory cmt. 3(b), at 498 (U.S. Sent’g Comm’n 2021).Show More courts have reasoned that any new term of imprisonment imposed punishes the defendant’s failure to comply with the judge’s order setting conditions of supervised release.120 120.E.g., United States v. Watters, 947 F.3d 493, 497–98 (8th Cir. 2020).Show More Because the punishment imposed is divorced from the new offense conduct, those courts have reasoned, the proceeding is distinguishable from a prosecution.

In United States v. Haymond, the Supreme Court’s most recent tangle with the constitutionality of Section 3583, the Court (specifically, a controlling concurrence) endorsed that rationale. Haymond concerned a challenge to the constitutionality of Section 3583(k), which provided that a judge who finds “by a preponderance of the evidence that a defendant on supervised release committed one of several enumerated offenses, including the possession of child pornography” must impose a sentence of at least five years’ imprisonment.121 121.139 S. Ct. 2369, 2374 (2019).Show More The petitioner in Haymond, who had been sentenced to serve an additional five years in prison for violating a condition of supervised release, challenged his conviction and sentence as violative of the Fifth and Sixth Amendments as interpreted in Apprendi. Noting that the petitioner had been subjected to an increased statutory maximum penalty based solely on a judge’s findings by a preponderance of the evidence, a plurality of the Supreme Court agreed.122 122.Id.Show More

Concurring solely in the judgment, Justice Breyer disagreed with the idea of “transplant[ing] the Apprendi line of cases to the supervised-release context.”123 123.Id. at 2385 (Breyer, J., concurring).Show More Nevertheless, he agreed that Section 3583(k) was unconstitutional. Unlike an ordinary revocation proceeding, which properly sanctioned “the defendant’s ‘breach of trust’—his ‘failure to follow the court-imposed conditions’ that followed his initial conviction,” Section 3583(k) was “more like punishment for a new offense, to which the jury right would typically attach.”124 124.Id. at 2386.In reaching that conclusion, Justice Breyer relied in part on a policy statement from the U.S. Sentencing Guidelines Manual. In our view, such policy statements cannot shed any light on the reach of constitutional rights.Show More In other words, the dispositive question, for constitutional purposes, was the purpose of the new term of imprisonment: punishment for a breach of trust did not implicate the Sixth Amendment, whereas punishment for new criminal conduct certainly did.125 125.Although Justice Breyer’s concurrence appears designed to affirm on the narrowest possible ground, it is arguably a broader holding—instead of merely recognizing that revocation proceedings can constitute sentencing proceedings, it recognizes that they can constitute prosecutions.Show More Following Haymond, courts of appeals rejected a number of Sixth Amendment challenges to the statute by citing to that concurrence, concluding that because revocation punished a defendant’s breach of trust—rather than the violation conduct itself—it was constitutionally sound.126 126.United States v. Peguero, 34 F.4th 143, 159 n.13 (2d Cir. 2022) (collecting cases).Show More

IV. The Constitutional Work Arounds Do Not Work

In our view, each of the primary arguments advanced to distinguish revocation proceedings from prosecutions to which the Sixth Amendment applies is without merit. Turning first to the rationale that revocation is part of the original penalty, the idea that, because “a term of supervised release is imposed as part and parcel of the original sentence,” post-revocation sanctions are “part of the penalty for the initial offense” certainly has intuitive appeal: supervised release was imposed as part of the original sentence, and the defendant was warned at sentencing of the consequences for violating the conditions set by a judge.127 127.Id. at 160–61 (quoting Johnson v. United States, 529 U.S. 694, 700–01 (2000)) (citing United States v. McNeil, 415 F.3d 273, 277 (2d Cir. 2005)).Show More

That rationale, however, ignores the plain text and legislative history of the SRA, which carefully delineates a term of supervised release from a term of imprisonment.128 128.18 U.S.C. § 3583(a).Show More As the Supreme Court has explained, “[s]upervised release fulfills rehabilitative ends, distinct from those served by incarceration,”129 129.United States v. Johnson, 529 U.S. 53, 59 (2000); see also United States v. Aldeen, 792 F.3d 247, 252 (2d Cir. 2015) (“Supervised release is not, fundamentally, part of the punishment; rather, its focus is rehabilitation.”).Show More and “prison time is ‘not interchangeable’ with supervised release.”130 130.Mont v. United States, 139 S. Ct. 1826, 1833 (2019) (quoting Johnson, 529 U.S. at 59).Show More Under Section 3583(e), supervised release and imprisonment also serve different goals; Section 3583(e) excludes the need to “provide just punishment” from the factors a judge must consider in deciding whether to impose or to “revoke” supervised release.131 131.18 U.S.C. § 3583(e)(3) (cross-referencing 18 U.S.C. § 3553(a)(2)(B)–(D)); see also Tapia v. United States, 564 U.S. 319, 326 (2011) (noting that a court imposing a term of supervised release “may not take account of retribution . . . when imposing a term of supervised release”).Show More In short, the punitive part of the sentence has been completed by the time a judge is considering revocation. Any new punishment imposed therefore cannot logically be considered part of the penalty for the original offense or even “part of the whole matrix of punishment which arises out of a defendant’s original crimes.”132 132.United States v. Flora, 810 F. Supp. 841, 842 (W.D. Ky. 1993). Further, to the extent that courts have deemed that rationale binding precedent because of Johnson, Johnson neither considered nor decided the general applicability of the Fifth and Sixth Amendments in revocation proceedings; it considered instead whether application of amendments to the SRA constituted an ex post facto violation in certain cases. Accordingly, Johnson is not controlling with respect to the applicability in revocation proceedings of the Grand Jury and Double Jeopardy Clauses of the Fifth Amendment or of Sixth Amendment rights.Show More Instead, it can only reasonably be understood as new punishment for new conduct,133 133.As some courts have pointed out, there is, of course, a statutory connection between the original sentence and the revocation term—§ 3583(e) sets a statutory maximum term of imprisonment based on the class of the original offense. E.g., United States v. Peguero, 34 F.4th 143, 161 n.14 (2d Cir. 2022). As Professor Schuman explains, however, that does not render the term of imprisonment imposed similar to parole because “parole revocation literally restored the defendant’s original prison term” whereas “revocation of supervised release results in a new prison term limited by the class of the original conviction, not the original sentence.” Schuman, supra note 108, at 172.Show More and thus violative of the Grand Jury and Double Jeopardy Clauses of the Fifth Amendment.

Similarly, the argument that revocation merely sanctions a breach of trust is unsupportable. More specifically, a judge who imposes a term of supervised release is not granting a defendant a reprieve from imprisonment in exchange for the defendant’s promise to comply with the conditions the judge sets. Instead, that judge is imposing an additional period of surveillance that begins only after the entire prison term she imposes has been served. Supervised release is therefore best understood as the opposite of trust.134 134.As Professor Schuman recognizes,[There is] one situation in which revocation of supervised release might be considered punishment for a breach of trust. If a judge sentenced a defendant to a shorter term of imprisonment in exchange for imposing a longer term of supervised release, then that substitution of supervision for imprisonment could be considered an act of trust, and violating a condition could be viewed as a breach of that trust.Schuman, supra note 108, at 174. But, as noted above, judges impose sentences of supervised release in the vast majority of cases, and, furthermore, “[n]either the supervised-release statute nor the sentencing guidelines require courts to exchange incarceration for supervision.” Id.; see also Jacob Schuman, Revocation and Retribution, 96 Wash. L. Rev. 881, 908–09 (2021) (arguing mandatory minimum terms of both imprisonment and supervision often make it impossible for judges to reduce one penalty in favor of the other).Show More As a result, any post-revocation term of imprisonment cannot logically be understood to punish anything other than the new violation conduct.135 135.Although Johnson “treat[s]” supervised release sentences as “part of the penalty for the initial offense,” 529 U.S. at 700, that treatment actually creates the double jeopardy problem of twice punishing the same offense described above.Show More

Moreover, even accepting the premise of the argument that revocation merely punishes failure to follow court orders, federal judges are not all-powerful despots with the authority to summarily imprison a person who disappoints them or breaches their trust. To be sure, judges have the statutory authority to punish persons for criminal contempt and to imprison or fine them for that contempt. But as discussed above, contempt proceedings require nearly all of the fundamental rights applicable to an ordinary prosecution. Therefore, even assuming that a post-revocation penalty merely sanctions the failure to follow a court order, the contempt authority does not justify the summary proceedings currently employed to adjudicate supervised release violations.

Finally, the argument that those on supervised release are entitled only to “conditional liberty” elides the fundamental distinctions between supervised release and parole. To be sure, the liberty of one serving a term of supervised release is “conditional” in one sense—failing to comply with conditions set by the sentencing judge may lead to imprisonment. But that is not the “conditional liberty” described by Morrissey or Gagnon. Both of those decisions considered systems in which a defendant received a benefit—freedom—in exchange for her promise to abide by certain restrictions. That grant of liberty was “conditioned” on compliance with those restrictions and could be revoked if the defendant failed to hold up her end of the agreement.136 136.See 18 U.S.C. § 3564(e) (sentence of probation is “conditional and subject to revocation”).Show More Supervised release, by contrast, involves no reprieve from prison granted in exchange for a defendant’s good behavior. In the context of supervised release, the necessary “condition” never exists. As a result, the “conditional” liberty to which a defendant is subject is distinct from the contractual-like liberty described by Morrissey and Gagnon.

Furthermore, Morrissey did not suggest that an individual on parole somehow forfeited constitutional protections by virtue of being on parole; instead, the Court reasoned that, once the government had successfully prosecuted an individual for a crime, it should not have to go through that burdensome process once again only to reimpose the same sentence a judge had previously imposed. Supervised release, by contrast, does not authorize a judge or parole board to afford a reprieve from prison in exchange for compliance with certain conditions. As a result, the “revocation” of supervised release is simply a new punishment, triggered by the commission of new wrongful conduct. To suggest that one on supervised release is entitled to lesser constitutional protections by virtue of having been convicted of the original offense, then, is to say that a criminal conviction cancels a person’s right to constitutional protections in any future prosecution. Surely, that cannot be the case.137 137.Under that rationale, a supervisee enjoys constitutional rights when indicted in state or federal court, but not when facing a significant term of incarceration for violating supervised release. The limit or grant of constitutional rights therefore would turn entirely on a prosecutor’s decision regarding how to pursue imprisonment—by going through the trouble of securing a federal indictment and formally charging a crime, or by simply asking the sentencing judge to revoke the term of supervised release.Show More

Conclusion

Those who drafted the Fifth and Sixth Amendments did so with the goal of making it difficult for the government to arbitrarily imprison a person. The current supervised release system offers prosecutors and courts what amounts to an end run around those carefully crafted protections, an expedient route to imprisonment that avoids the inconveniences of obtaining an indictment, affording the right to jury trial, and proving guilt beyond a reasonable doubt. In our view, it is that very expediency that violates the Constitution, harming not only those whose constitutional rights are denied, but also eroding—prosecution by prosecution—the constitutional structure put in place by the Framers to protect ordinary citizens from the misuse of government power.

  1. Sentencing Reform Act of 1984, Pub. L. No. 98-473, tit. II, ch. 2, 98 Stat. 1987 (codified as amended in scattered sections of 18 and 28 U.S.C.); Fiona Doherty, Indeterminate Sentencing Returns: The Invention of Supervised Release, 88 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 958, 996–97 (2013). Professor Doherty’s seminal piece provides a thorough overview of the story of supervised release.

  2. Id. at 983–84.

  3. Id. at 984.

  4. Id. at 985; see also Peter B. Hoffman, History of the Federal Parole System: Part 1 (1910–1972), 61 Fed. Prob. 23, 27 (1997) (explaining that parole decisions were made by the whole board).

  5. Parole Act, ch. 387, §§ 1, 3, 36 Stat. 819 (1910), repealed by Sentencing Reform Act of 1984, § 212(a)(2).

  6. Id. § 3.

  7. Hoffman, supra note 4, at 28.

  8. Id.

  9. Id.

  10. E.g., Clark v. Stevens, 291 F.2d 388, 389 (6th Cir. 1961); Hiatt v. Compagna, 178 F.2d 42, 45 (5th Cir. 1949) (“A prisoner sentenced to the penitentiary is turned over by the court to the executive, namely the Attorney General, to have the sentence executed. . . . It is very evident that the whole matter of paroles is left to the informed discretion of the Board. Court action is not made a part of it.”).

  11. Comment, The Parole System, 120 U. Pa. L. Rev. 282, 287–88 (1971); see also Anderson v. Corall, 263 U.S. 193, 196 (1923) (“While on parole the convict is bound to remain in the legal custody and under the control of the warden until the expiration of the term, less allowance, if any, for good conduct. While this is an amelioration of punishment, it is in legal effect imprisonment.”); Padilla v. Lynch, 398 F.2d 481, 482 (9th Cir. 1968) (stating that, because parole is a form of custody, a complaint alleging that the denial of parole violated the equal protection clause is insufficient).

  12. Comment, supra note 11, at 286–87; cf. Ughbanks v. Armstrong, 208 U.S. 481, 488 (1908) (describing a state’s grant of parole as “the granting of a favor to a convicted criminal confined within one of its prisons”).

  13. Hyser v. Reed, 318 F.2d 225, 237 (D.C. Cir. 1963) (rejecting Sixth Amendment challenge to parole revocation procedures); see also Comment, supra note 11, at 288–89 (stating that the board and the parolee have a shared interest in rehabilitating the parolee).

  14. 408 U.S. 471, 472 (1972).

  15. Id. at 474–75.

  16. Id. at 480.

  17. Id.

  18. Id.

  19. Id. at 483; see also Jacob Schuman, Supervised Release Is Not Parole, 53 Loy. L.A. L. Rev. 587, 624 (2020).

  20. Morrissey, 408 U.S. at 482.

  21. Id.

  22. Id. at 489.

  23. Fed. R. Crim. P. 32.1 advisory committee’s note to 1979 and 1989 amendments.

  24. Ex parte United States, 242 U.S. 27, 37 (1916); see also Brent E. Newton, The Story of Federal Probation, 53 Am. Crim. L. Rev. 311, 313 (2016) (noting that federal court judges would suspend prison sentences prior to the passing of the Probation Act).

  25. Newton, supra note 24, at 312.

  26. Fiona Doherty, Obey All Laws and Be Good: Probation and the Meaning of Recidivism, 104 Geo. L.J. 291, 330, 335 (2016).

  27. 411 U.S. 778, 779 (1973).

  28. Id. at 780.

  29. Id. at 781.

  30. Mempa v. Rhay, 389 U.S. 128, 135 (1967).

  31. Id. at 137.

  32. Gagnon, 411 U.S. at 779.

  33. Id. at 782.

  34. Id. at 789.

  35. Id. at 782.

  36. S. Rep. No. 98-225, at 59 (1983). Arguably, then, Mempa is the only Supreme Court decision that affords constitutional guidance with regard to modern federal probation, which is a sentence in its own right and which requires a judge to engage in a full-blown sentencing proceeding when probation is “revoked.”

  37. United States v. Labonte, 520 U.S. 751, 769 (1997) (Breyer, J., dissenting).

  38. Doherty, supra note 1, at 995.

  39. Sentencing Reform Act of 1984, Pub. L. No. 98-473, tit. II, ch. 2, sec. 212(a)(2), § 3583(a), 98 Stat. 1987, 1999 (codified as amended at 18 U.S.C. § 3583(a)) (“The court, in imposing a sentence to a term of imprisonment for a felony or a misdemeanor, may include as a part of the sentence a requirement that the defendant be placed on a term of supervised release after imprisonment.” (emphasis added)). Imposition of a term of supervised release was required as part of every sentence that imposed imprisonment during the mandatory Sentencing Guidelines era. Since Booker, with few exceptions, imposition of supervised release is discretionary. Nonetheless, it is imposed in the vast majority of federal sentences. See Christine S. Scott-Hayward, Shadow Sentencing: The Imposition of Federal Supervised Release, 18 Berkeley J. Crim. L. 180, 186 (2013).

  40. S. Rep. No. 98-225, at 123 (1983) (emphasis added).

  41. Id. at 124.

  42. Doherty, supra note 1, at 998.

  43. § 3583(d), 98 Stat. at 1999.

  44. Doherty, supra note 1, at 999–1000.

  45. Id. at 1000.

  46. Id.

  47. Id. at 1001; see 18 U.S.C. § 3583(e)(3); Fed. R. Crim. P. 32.1.

  48. Doherty, supra note 1, at 1002.

  49. Id. at 1001.

  50. Schuman, supra note 19, at 615–16, 615 n.200 (collecting appellate cases).

  51. As United States District Judge Jack Weinstein recognized, even the term “revoke” is a “misnomer” in the context of supervised release. Because supervised release does not replace imprisonment, a judge who “revokes” a term of supervised release is not taking back the freedom she previously bestowed. United States v. Trotter, 321 F. Supp. 3d 337, 346–47 (E.D.N.Y. 2018).

  52. Dissenting in United States v. Haymond, discussed further in Part III, Justice Alito posited that supervised release is equivalent to a sentence of parole:

    [A] defendant sentenced to x years of imprisonment followed by y years of supervised release is really sentenced to a maximum punishment of x + y years of confinement, with the proviso that any time beyond x years will be excused if the defendant abides by the terms of supervised release.

    139 S. Ct. 2369, 2390 (2019). But that argument ignores the plain text of the statute, which carefully distinguishes between a term of supervised release and imprisonment. It also ignores the legislative history of the SRA, which makes clear that supervised release was designed to serve a different purpose than imprisonment and was not intended to be interchangeable with imprisonment. Finally, there is no evidence that judges in practice exchange supervised release for imprisonment by imposing shorter prison sentences when they elect to include a term of supervised release as part of a sentence. Empirical evidence instead suggests that many judges routinely impose prison sentences within the range contemplated by the Sentencing Guidelines—which, of course, similarly do not anticipate that shorter prison terms should be imposed where a judge elects to impose a term of supervised release. See Christine S. Scott-Hayward, supra note 39, at 186 (2013); U.S. Sentencing Commission Guidelines Manual, ch. 5, introductory cmt., pt. A, sent’g tbl; pt. B, introductory cmt., § 5B1.1 cmt. background (2021).

  53. United States v. Peguero, 34 F.4th 143, 167 (2d Cir. 2022) (Underhill, J., dissenting); see also Rothgery v. Gillespie, 554 U.S. 191, 221–22 (2008) (Thomas, J., dissenting) (discussing elements of a prosecution).

  54. Green v. United States, 356 U.S. 165, 183 (1958).

  55. U.S. Const. amend. V.

  56. U.S. Const. amend. VI.

  57. U.S. Const. amend. V.

  58. Michael J. Zydney Mannheimer, Ripeness of Self-Incrimination Clause Disputes, 95 J. Crim. L. & Criminology 1261, 1321–22 (2005) (noting that the Fifth Amendment protections can apply before a formal prosecution has commenced).

  59. Hurtado v. California, 110 U.S. 516, 551–52 (1884) (Harlan, J., dissenting) (cleaned up) (emphasis added).

  60. U.S. Const. amend. V.

  61. Elizabeth T. Lear, Is Conviction Irrelevant?, 40 UCLA L. Rev. 1179, 1230 n.246 (1993); Wilkerson v. Whitley, 28 F.3d 498, 502 (5th Cir. 1994).

  62. Ex parte Wall, 107 U.S. 265, 298 (1882); see also Mahon v. Justice, 127 U.S. 700, 713 (1888) (noting that defendant was “held to answer the indictment” after formal charges were served upon him); United States v. McIntosh, 704 F.3d 894, 903–04 (11th Cir. 2013) (quoting Answer, Oxford English Dictionary, http://www.oed.com/view/Entry/8146 (last visited Dec. 21, 2012)) (observing that “answer” means “to speak in reply or opposition to a charge,” a definition recognized when the Fifth Amendment was adopted).

  63. United States v. Smith, 982 F.2d 757, 761 (2d Cir. 1992) (cleaned up) (citing, inter alia, Mackin v. United States, 117 U.S. 348 (1886)). Under federal law, persons sentenced to one year or less cannot serve their terms in a penitentiary without their consent. 18 U.S.C. § 4083.

  64. See also Fed. R. Crim. P. 7(a) (designating that crimes punishable by a term of imprisonment of more than one year must be charged by indictment).

  65. 18 U.S.C. § 3583(e)(3) (“[A] defendant whose term is revoked under this paragraph may not be required to serve on any such revocation more than 5 years in prison if the offense that resulted in the term of supervised release is a class A felony, more than 3 years in prison if such offense is a class B felony, more than 2 years in prison if such offense is a class C or D felony, or more than one year in any other case.”).

  66. See Fed. R. Crim. P. 32.1.

  67. U.S. Const. amend. V.

  68. Id.

  69. Indeed, courts already acknowledge that the Due Process clause enshrined in the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments applies to revocation proceedings. See, e.g., United States v. Haymond, 139 S. Ct. 2369, 2391 (2019) (Alito, J., dissenting).

  70. E.g., United States v. Peguero, 34 F.4th 143, 157–58 (2d Cir. 2022) (citing exclusively Sixth Amendment cases for the proposition that no right to indictment attaches); United States v. Cordova, 461 F.3d 1184, 1185–90 (10th Cir. 2006) (concluding that there is no Sixth [sic] Amendment right to indictment, and citing Morrissey v. Brewer, 408 U.S. 471, 480 (1972)). Although some courts have held that imposing a term of supervised release to follow a prison sentence of less than a year does not transform a misdemeanor conviction into a felony conviction, that does not answer the question whether one facing more than a year of imprisonment upon revocation is entitled to be indicted. See, e.g., United States v. Celestine, 905 F.2d 59, 60–61 (5th Cir. 1990) (per curiam); United States v. Purvis, 940 F.2d 1276, 1280 (9th Cir. 1991).

  71. U.S. Const. amend. V.

  72. Apprendi v. New Jersey, 530 U.S. 466, 510 (2000) (Thomas, J., concurring) (citing 1 Joel Prentiss Bishop, Commentaries on the Law of Criminal Procedure § 80, at 51, § 84, at 53 (2d ed. 1872)); see also Haymond, 139 S. Ct. at 2376 (describing the concept of a “crime” as broad and linked to punishment); Green v. United States, 356 U.S. 165, 202 (1958) (Black, J., dissenting) (“How can it possibly be any more of a crime to be convicted of disobeying a statute and sent to jail for three years than to be found guilty of violating a judicial decree forbidding precisely the same conduct and imprisoned for the same term?”).

  73. Apprendi, 530 U.S. at 501 (Thomas, J., concurring) (observing that a crime “includes every fact that is by law a basis for imposing or increasing punishment (in contrast with a fact that mitigates punishment)”).

  74. Kennedy v. Mendoza-Martinez, 372 U.S. 144, 167 (1963); see also Hudson v. United States, 522 U.S. 93, 99 (1997) (noting that a court must utilize tools of statutory construction to determine whether a law is sufficiently punitive to transform a civil remedy into a criminal penalty).

  75. Apprendi, 530 U.S. at 510 (Thomas, J., concurring) (cleaned up) (citing 1 Joel Prentiss Bishop, Commentaries on the Law of Criminal Procedure § 80, 51 (2d ed. 1872)).

  76. 18 U.S.C. § 3583(e).

  77. See, e.g., Mendoza-Martinez, 372 U.S. at 167 (“[F]orfeiture of citizenship is a penalty for the act of leaving or staying outside the country to avoid the draft. This being so, the Fifth and Sixth Amendments mandate that this punishment cannot be imposed without a prior criminal trial and all its incidents, including indictment, notice, confrontation, jury trial, assistance of counsel, and compulsory process for obtaining witnesses. If the sanction these sections impose is punishment, and it plainly is, the procedural safeguards required as incidents of a criminal prosecution are lacking.”).

  78. See infra Part III.A (discussing the “original penalty” rationale). That rationale overlooks the statutes respectively authorizing a sentence of probation and a sentence of imprisonment. Compare 18 U.S.C. § 3564(e) (“A sentence of probation remains conditional and subject to revocation until its expiration or termination.” (emphasis ours)), with id. § 3582(b) (“Notwithstanding the fact that a sentence to imprisonment can subsequently be [modified due to compassionate release or corrected or appealed,] a judgment of conviction that includes such a sentence [of imprisonment] constitutes a final judgment for all other purposes.”) and id. § 3582(c) (instructing that with rare exceptions, a “court may not modify a term of imprisonment once it has been imposed”).

  79. Stirone v. United States, 361 U.S. 212, 218 (1960).

  80. Id. at 215–16; United States v. Simmons, 11 F.4th 239, 268 (4th Cir. 2021) (“[I]ncongruity between the indictment and the conviction that a constructive amendment causes destroys the defendant’s substantial right to be tried only on charges presented in the indictment.” (cleaned up) (quoting Stirone, 361 U.S. at 217)).

  81. Some decisions hold that, when an indictment fails to charge one of the elements of a charged offense, but there is overwhelming evidence in support of the missing element, the right to indictment is not violated. E.g., United States v. Nkansah, 699 F.3d 743, 752 (2d Cir. 2012) (citing United States v. Cotton, 535 U.S. 625, 633 (2002)). Of course, supervised release violation conduct is not an element of any offense actually charged in the underlying indictment, but instead entirely new and separate conduct that can occur years (or even decades) after the original indictment.

  82. North Carolina v. Pearce, 395 U.S. 711, 717 (1969), overruled on other grounds by Alabama v. Smith, 490 U.S. 794, 798 (1989); see also Ex parte Lange, 85 U.S. 163, 173 (1873) (“[T]he Constitution was designed as much to prevent the criminal from being twice punished for the same offence as from being twice tried for it.”).

  83. Missouri v. Hunter, 459 U.S. 359, 368–69 (1983) (Marshall, J., dissenting) (“Where, as here, a legislature specifically authorizes cumulative punishment under two statutes . . . the prosecutor may seek and the trial court or jury may impose cumulative punishment under such statutes in a single trial.”).

  84. In the Sentencing Reform Act, Congress “forbade the federal courts from ‘modify[ing] a term of imprisonment once it has been imposed.’” United States v. Jones, 980 F.3d 1098, 1103–04 (6th Cir. 2020) (quoting Sentencing Reform Act of 1984, Pub. L. No. 98–473, tit. II, ch. 2, § 212(a), 98 Stat. 1987, 1998). To avoid constitutional problems, when courts are authorized to modify sentences, they are limited to reducing sentences. See 18 U.S.C. § 3582(c).

  85. U.S. Const. amend. VI.

  86. Although the right to a speedy trial may attach before an indictment issues, each of the rights encompassed in the Sixth Amendment attaches by the time an indictment is returned. See United States v. Black, 918 F.3d 243, 256 (2d Cir. 2019).

  87. See, e.g., Rothgery v. Gillespie County, 554 U.S. 191, 219 (2008) (Thomas, J., dissenting) (citing to 4 William Blackstone, Commentaries *289, to discern the Framers’ intent); see also Sanjay Chhablani, Disentangling the Sixth Amendment, 11 U. Pa. J. Const. L. 487, 492 (2009) (noting the dearth of early Supreme Court opinions shedding light on the scope of Sixth Amendment protections).

  88. U.S. Const. amend. VI.

  89. Rothgery, 554 U.S. at 223 (Thomas, J., dissenting); see also United States v. Haymond, 139 S. Ct. 2369, 2376 (2019) (plurality opinion) (describing a prosecution as “the process of exhibiting formal charges against an offender before a legal tribunal” (cleaned up) (quoting Noah Webster, An American Dictionary of the English Language (1st ed. 1828))).

  90. Rothgery, 554 U.S. at 234 (Thomas, J., dissenting).

  91. Id. at 198 (quoting Kirby v. Illinois, 406 U.S. 682, 689 (1972)); see also Middendorf v. Henry, 425 U.S. 25, 40 (1976) (“Yet the adversary nature of civilian criminal proceedings is one of the touchstones of the Sixth Amendment’s right to counsel.”); Williams v. Florida, 399 U.S. 78, 112 (1970) (Black, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part) (noting that the Fifth and Sixth Amendments were designed “to shield the defendant against state power”).

  92. Note, An Argument for Confrontation under the Federal Sentencing Guidelines, 105 Harv. L. Rev. 1880, 1889 (1992) (arguing that the Sixth Amendment was “meant to apply” when “the state decides how to punish an individual for criminal behavior”); 4 William Blackstone, Commentaries *301 (defining a prosecution in part as “the next step towards the punishment of offenders”); Search for Collocate “Punish” Within Four Words of “Prosecute”, Brigham Young University’s Corpus of Founding Era American English, Version 6.1.0, https://lawcorp​us.byu.edu/byucoeme/concordances (last visited Oct. 17, 2022) (thirteen hits) (enter query term “prosecute” in main search bar; then enter “punish” under the “collocates” tab below, with “scope left” and “scope right” set to four; then click “apply changes”).

  93. Rothgery, 554 U.S. at 234 (Thomas, J., dissenting).

  94. U.S. Const. amend. VI.

  95. United States v. Haymond, 139 S. Ct. 2369, 2376 (2019) (plurality opinion) (cleaned up); see also id. at 2392 (defining the accused as “an individual ‘[c]harged with a crime, by a legal process’”) (Alito, J., dissenting) (quoting Noah Webster, An American Dictionary of the English Language (1828)). Dissenting in Haymond, Justice Alito argued that one serving a term of supervised release is no longer the “accused,” but has instead been properly convicted of the underlying offense, and that any sanctions imposed for violation conduct merely sanction a breach of the court’s trust. Id. at 2392–93. As a result, he argued, the Sixth Amendment was inapplicable. Id. at 2392. But as Justice Alito also recognized, the original prosecution has ended by the time a revocation proceeding begins. Id. at 2393–95. And as discussed further below, there is no statutory support for the idea that revocation sanctions a defendant’s breach of the court’s trust. Instead, revocation can only reasonably be understood to sanction the new offense conduct—meaning one charged with a supervised release violation stands in the shoes of the “accused,” for Sixth Amendment purposes. And although the underlying criminal conviction may certainly deprive one of certain constitutional rights, the right to be indicted and the right to trial by jury for a new prosecution are not among them. Cf. Strunk v. United States, 412 U.S. 434, 437–38 (1973) (acknowledging that defendant had the right to a speedy trial irrespective of the fact that he was incarcerated in a penitentiary on an unrelated charge). As a result, the mere fact that a releasee stands convicted of the crime giving rise to the term of supervised release does not afford the government the right to deprive her of Fifth and Sixth Amendment rights in a new prosecution.

  96. Rothgery, 554 U.S. at 233 (Thomas, J., dissenting) (quoting Kirby v. Illinois, 406 U.S. 682, 689 (1972)).

  97. Doherty, supra note 1, at 1003.

  98. Id. at 1003–04.

  99. Id. at 1004.

  100. Id. at 1006–07.

  101. E.g., United States v. Beals, 87 F.3d 854, 859 (7th Cir. 1996) (concluding that revocation had to sanction the original offense because “[c]onduct that violates the terms of supervised release, like that of parole violations, is often not criminal”); United States v. Meeks, 25 F.3d 1117, 1123 (2d Cir. 1994) (relying in part on the lack of “fundamental constitutional procedural protections” in a revocation proceeding to conclude that it must be punishing the original offense).

  102. Specifically, Johnson concerned a challenge to the application of § 3583(h), which authorized a district court to (1) revoke a term of supervised release; (2) impose a term of imprisonment; and (3) impose a new term of supervised release to follow imprisonment. 529 U.S. 694, 696 (2000).

  103. Id. at 700.

  104. Id.

  105. Id. The double-jeopardy problem the Court identified in Johnson involved punishing violation conduct both as a supervised release violation and as the basis for a new prosecution. The Court did not consider the double-jeopardy problems discussed above—the fact that the imposition of an additional penalty for the original crime also violates the Double Jeopardy Clause.

  106. Johnson did not make that point explicitly; it did, however, cite to Gagnon to suggest that revocation was not akin to a prosecution. Id. at 700–01.

  107. Id. at 700.

  108. Id. at 713; see also Jacob Schuman, Criminal Violations, 108 Va. L. Rev. (forthcoming Dec. 2022) (manuscript at 125) (on file with authors) (noting the Court’s evasion of that constitutional obstacle and its adoption of the “original offense” doctrine could be seen as dicta).

  109. United States v. Peguero, 34 F.4th 143, 160 (2d Cir. 2022); see also United States v. Jackson, 559 F.3d 368, 371 (5th Cir. 2009) (“Post-revocation sanctions are not a separate penalty for purposes of the Double Jeopardy clause—they are part of the penalty for the original offense.”); United States v. Gavilanes-Ocaranza, 772 F.3d 624, 627 (9th Cir. 2014) (“The revocation of supervised release is not a criminal prosecution for Sixth Amendment purposes, because the violation ‘simply triggers the execution of the conditions of the original sentence.’” (quoting United States v. Paskow, 11 F.3d 873, 881 (9th Cir. 1993))); United States v. Doka, 955 F.3d 290, 294 (2d Cir. 2020) (noting defendants in supervised release proceedings are not entitled to holding the government to a burden of proof beyond a reasonable doubt or to a trial by jury).

  110. 530 U.S. 466 (2000).

  111. Id. at 490.

  112. The Supreme Court followed up Apprendi with Blakely v. Washington, in which it clarified that “‘the statutory maximum’ for Apprendi purposes is the maximum sentence a judge may impose solely on the basis of the facts reflected in the jury verdict or admitted by the defendant.” 542 U.S. 296, 303 (2004) (emphasis omitted). Relying in part on that holding, the Court then decided United States v. Booker, in which it held that § 3553(b), which made the Guidelines mandatory and binding on district courts, was unconstitutional. 543 U.S. 220, 245 (2005).

  113. E.g., United States v. McIntosh, 630 F.3d 699, 702–03 (7th Cir. 2011); see also United States v. Huerta-Pimental, 445 F.3d 1220, 1222–25 (9th Cir. 2006) (holding Apprendi has no effect on the imposition of supervised release under § 3583); United States v. Work, 409 F.3d 484, 489–92 (1st Cir. 2005) (rejecting the defendant’s argument that the inclusion of a term of supervised release as a part of his original sentence exposed him to additional punishment beyond the statutory maximum).

  114. United States v. Cunningham, 607 F.3d 1264, 1266–67 (11th Cir. 2010); United States v. Carlton, 442 F.3d 802, 807 (2d Cir. 2006).

  115. 442 F.3d at 807.

  116. Id. at 809.

  117. Id. at 809–10.

  118. E.g., Cunningham, 607 F.3d at 1267–68.

  119. U.S. Sent’g Guidelines Manual ch. 7, pt. A, introductory cmt. 3(b), at 498 (U.S. Sent’g Comm’n 2021).

  120. E.g., United States v. Watters, 947 F.3d 493, 497–98 (8th Cir. 2020).

  121. 139 S. Ct. 2369, 2374 (2019).

  122. Id.

  123. Id. at 2385 (Breyer, J., concurring).

  124. Id. at 2386. In reaching that conclusion, Justice Breyer relied in part on a policy statement from the U.S. Sentencing Guidelines Manual. In our view, such policy statements cannot shed any light on the reach of constitutional rights.

  125. Although Justice Breyer’s concurrence appears designed to affirm on the narrowest possible ground, it is arguably a broader holding—instead of merely recognizing that revocation proceedings can constitute sentencing proceedings, it recognizes that they can constitute prosecutions.

  126. United States v. Peguero, 34 F.4th 143, 159 n.13 (2d Cir. 2022) (collecting cases).

  127. Id. at 160–61 (quoting Johnson v. United States, 529 U.S. 694, 700–01 (2000)) (citing United States v. McNeil, 415 F.3d 273, 277 (2d Cir. 2005)).

  128. 18 U.S.C. § 3583(a).

  129. United States v. Johnson, 529 U.S. 53, 59 (2000); see also United States v. Aldeen, 792 F.3d 247, 252 (2d Cir. 2015) (“Supervised release is not, fundamentally, part of the punishment; rather, its focus is rehabilitation.”).

  130. Mont v. United States, 139 S. Ct. 1826, 1833 (2019) (quoting Johnson, 529 U.S. at 59).

  131. 18 U.S.C. § 3583(e)(3) (cross-referencing 18 U.S.C. § 3553(a)(2)(B)–(D)); see also Tapia v. United States, 564 U.S. 319, 326 (2011) (noting that a court imposing a term of supervised release “may not take account of retribution . . . when imposing a term of supervised release”).

  132. United States v. Flora, 810 F. Supp. 841, 842 (W.D. Ky. 1993). Further, to the extent that courts have deemed that rationale binding precedent because of Johnson, Johnson neither considered nor decided the general applicability of the Fifth and Sixth Amendments in revocation proceedings; it considered instead whether application of amendments to the SRA constituted an ex post facto violation in certain cases. Accordingly, Johnson is not controlling with respect to the applicability in revocation proceedings of the Grand Jury and Double Jeopardy Clauses of the Fifth Amendment or of Sixth Amendment rights.

  133. As some courts have pointed out, there is, of course, a statutory connection between the original sentence and the revocation term—§ 3583(e) sets a statutory maximum term of imprisonment based on the class of the original offense. E.g., United States v. Peguero, 34 F.4th 143, 161 n.14 (2d Cir. 2022). As Professor Schuman explains, however, that does not render the term of imprisonment imposed similar to parole because “parole revocation literally restored the defendant’s original prison term” whereas “revocation of supervised release results in a new prison term limited by the class of the original conviction, not the original sentence.” Schuman, supra note 108, at 172.

  134. As Professor Schuman recognizes,

    [There is] one situation in which revocation of supervised release might be considered punishment for a breach of trust. If a judge sentenced a defendant to a shorter term of imprisonment in exchange for imposing a longer term of supervised release, then that substitution of supervision for imprisonment could be considered an act of trust, and violating a condition could be viewed as a breach of that trust.

    Schuman, supra note 108, at 174. But, as noted above, judges impose sentences of supervised release in the vast majority of cases, and, furthermore, “[n]either the supervised-release statute nor the sentencing guidelines require courts to exchange incarceration for supervision.” Id.; see also Jacob Schuman, Revocation and Retribution, 96 Wash. L. Rev. 881, 908–09 (2021) (arguing mandatory minimum terms of both imprisonment and supervision often make it impossible for judges to reduce one penalty in favor of the other).

  135. Although Johnson “treat[s]” supervised release sentences as “part of the penalty for the initial offense,” 529 U.S. at 700, that treatment actually creates the double jeopardy problem of twice punishing the same offense described above.

  136. See 18 U.S.C. § 3564(e) (sentence of probation is “conditional and subject to revocation”).

  137. Under that rationale, a supervisee enjoys constitutional rights when indicted in state or federal court, but not when facing a significant term of incarceration for violating supervised release. The limit or grant of constitutional rights therefore would turn entirely on a prosecutor’s decision regarding how to pursue imprisonment—by going through the trouble of securing a federal indictment and formally charging a crime, or by simply asking the sentencing judge to revoke the term of supervised release.