Foreword

On August 11 and 12, 2017, Charlottesville, Virginia—the home of the University of Virginia and this journal—played unwitting host to two days of white nationalist and neo-Nazi rallies and violence. For those of us in Charlottesville, those events were intensely personal and local. The white nationalists and neo-Nazis violated our physical space. They maimed and killed members of our community. They threatened the security and sense of belonging of our neighbors, colleagues, students, and friends. And they challenged the values of equality and tolerance we hold dear.

From the moment the events unfolded, it was clear that they resonated beyond Charlottesville itself. Such blatant forms of white supremacy came as a surprise to many. They preoccupied observers far flung from Charlottesville both for the violence and loss of life on display and for the stark evidence they provided of deep and enduring fault lines within our nation and our society. The intolerance and hate the white nationalists and neo-Nazis exhibited most directly and explicitly targeted Jews and African Americans, but their reach was far broader. Their intent to make vulnerable all those who do not conform to their image was potent and palpable. Moreover, the incident implicated numerous questions for the law, for politics, and for society itself. The discussions that followed engaged questions not only of race, religion, ethnicity, and nationality, but also of gender and sexuality, pluralism and tolerance, politics and civic engagement, social justice and economic opportunity, speech and violence, civility and protest and counter-protest, and more.

This symposium focuses on the racial implications and reverberations of August 11-12. The conference that produced these articles brought an annual national meeting of empirical critical race theorists to Charlottesville to train their considerable intellectual talents on the first anniversary of August 11-12. The resulting scholarship asks what we can learn from August 11-12 about the legal underpinnings of white supremacy in the United States, from the beginning of its history to the violence in 2017 and beyond. It investigates the surprise with which so many responded to August 11-12 and shows us why we should not be surprised.

The Future is Almost Here: Inaction is Actually Mistaken Action

Professor Ryan Calo has written a response to our article appearing in the current issue of the Virginia Law Review, Automated Vehicles and Manufacturer Responsibility for Accidents: A New Legal Regime for a New Era,[1] in which we develop the proposition that the United States is on the verge of a new era in transportation, requiring a new legal regime. As many commentators have noted, over the coming decades, there will be a revolution in driving, as manually-driven cars are replaced by automated vehicles (AVs).[2] There will then be a radically new world of auto accidents: most accidents will be caused by cars, not by drivers.

In a world of accidents dominated by AVs, current tort doctrine, in our view, will be anachronistic and obsolete. We present a proposal for a more effective system, adopting strict manufacturer responsibility for auto accidents. We call this system Manufacturer Enterprise Responsibility, or “MER.” In describing and developing our proposal for MER, we present a detailed, extensively analyzed approach that would promote deterrence and compensation more effectively than continued reliance on tort in the coming world of auto accidents.[3] MER would be a manufacturer-financed, strict responsibility bodily injury compensation system, administered by a fund created through assessments levied on AV manufacturers.

Professor Calo does not disagree with the framework of our proposal—which he describes as “sensible and well thought out”[4]—but takes a different tack: arguing that legal scholarship, such as our proposal, has limited capacity to anticipate the future of unfolding law and technology. Here, we respond to his main points.

We agree with Professor Calo’s opening supposition that proposing policymaking about issues that may take decades to become ripe may well be like imagining, in the 1950s, what it would be like to commute to Mars. But this analogy is seriously misleading, because AVs are already on the roads being tested. It is as if we were already traveling to Mars on an experimental basis, with routine trips back and forth being planned for the near future. We cannot afford to wait and see what the future brings over a period of decades; a world in which there are privately owned AVs being operated on highways and city streets is just over the horizon. The failure to do something about that is not the equivalent of keeping our policymaking powder dry. Similarly, Professor Calo’s caution that AVs represent a “qualitatively distinct affordance”[5]—both in vehicle design (absence of steering wheels, gas and brake pedals, and so on), and traffic patterns (of commuting and congestion)—has no bearing on the fact that vehicular injuries will still occur, even if in reduced number, which will need to be addressed by accident law.

In this regard, the current liability regime will apply to AVs unless affirmative steps are taken to adopt a different regime. Given the distinct issues and problems that accidents involving AVs will pose, products liability law will be making a “sweeping intervention[],”[6] to reference Professor Calo’s cautionary note, into the world of AV accidents, whether we like it or not. The question is whether we simply let that happen even though we can predict that passively allowing this intervention will have negative consequences, or we devise an intervention that will have more positive consequences than watching as the current system is less and less capable of handling AV accidents. This leaves us with two options.  We could let the transition take place and watch our current system become less and less capable of handling the new regime, or we can devise an intervention that addresses the challenges we will face. As our article indicates, the serious difficulties posed at present in design defects cases will be greatly exacerbated in assigning liability in conventional products liability terms in the context of the esoterica of safety-generating algorithms and machine learning.[7]

It may be, as Professor Calo imagines, that Google and Uber, rather than auto manufacturers, will become the central players in developing AVs. But some entity will still have to make the vehicles, and they will consist of both software developed by the Googles and Ubers of this world and hardware made by the vehicle manufacturers. Google and Uber are not likely to be manufacturing brakes, tires, and air bags. If Google and Uber are responsible only for accidents caused by software, and Ford, GM, and Toyota are solely responsible for accidents caused by hardware, retaining conventional products liability will generate the very litigation nightmare that MER is designed to avoid.[8] Under our approach, if it turns out that Google and Uber rather than Ford and Toyota should be responsible for all accidents “arising out of the operation of HAVs,”[9] then our proposal can be transposed so that Google and Uber are responsible for contributions to the MER fund.[10] The basic rationale for our proposal will still be applicable.

Professor Calo also is concerned that, at some point in the unforeseeable future, individuals will not own AVs. Instead, third parties such as Google, Uber, or cities will own them. He seems to think that our assumption that “individuals will own and insure their own cars,”[11] if incorrect, will undermine our proposal—for example, because we deliberately omit protection against property damage from MER. But so what? Nothing turns on this. Ride-sharing owners would also presumably have to decide whether to buy property (collision and comprehensive) insurance or to self-insure. Whether these entities or individuals have to make that decision would not change anything of consequence.

He also comments that the “incentive structure of an app-based technology company that both owns and operates its vehicles differs rather markedly from that of a car manufacturer that sells vehicles to people.”[12] Perhaps, but in what relevant respects? No one thinks that products liability law generates different incentives for conglomerates than for single-product companies. Why should there be a difference in this regard between technology companies and manufacturers? If there is an insight here, it eludes us.

The fact that “dramatically distinct modalities of transportation”[13] could arise once there are a lot of AVs on the roads leads Professor Calo to argue against pre-empting state experimentation with a single national approach. We would concur in a qualified fashion. This concern is why MER would not be triggered until AVs constitute twenty-five percent of all registered vehicles. That condition is meant to provide ample time for social, cultural, and technological evolution to tell us what “transportation modalities” actually have developed. But there is a deeper point to be made here. If the world of tomorrow features flying drones and/or comprehensive mass transportation, that will be soon enough to rethink liability law. Should we remain frozen until then?

Relatedly, Professor Calo asks what assumptions we are making about the trajectory of law and technology or its social impact. In fact, we are making no assumptions. Why should we be addressing whether a MER-type system would apply to harms from surgical robots? Having said that, we agree that the theory underlying MER may extend “well beyond”[14] driverless cars. The theory could extend to other kinds of accidents as well. It might even be nice (though it might also be unwise, or even dangerous) to have a single, unified approach to compensation and liability for accidental physical harm. New Zealand has done that, with mixed results.[15] In the United States we have never done it. As a practical matter, it is impossible.

In the United States we almost always address one major social policy concern at a time, instead of trying to address all our problems at once. Workers’ compensation is illustrative, even though the theory underlying workers’ compensation might also have applied to other settings. Similarly, auto no-fault compensation is grounded in the motor vehicle context. It addresses the cluster of issues associated with auto accidents, although some of these issues also arose, and still arise, in connection with injuries caused by defective products and harmful environmental exposures.

In the last few decades we have adopted a number of targeted compensation funds—the childhood vaccine-injury fund,[16] the 9/11 victim compensation fund,[17] and the birth-related neurological injury funds in Florida[18] and Virginia.[19] The principles underlying these approaches are not entirely consistent either, as one of us has repeatedly noted.[20] Since we are not going to have consistency across all of our liability and compensation regimes, deferring to lack of consistency—along with inability to predict long-term future scenarios of accident-generating technology—is a prescription for paralysis. Consequently, if in the future we need to think about applying MER to drone-related accidents, or robots performing surgery, we can face those issues as the need arises.

In short, because doing nothing about the law governing accidents involving AVs would actually constitute mistaken action, we should do the sensible thing. In our view, MER is exactly that.

 


[1] Kenneth S. Abraham & Robert L. Rabin, Automated Vehicles and Manufacturer Respon­sibility for Accidents: A New Legal Regime for a New Era, 105 Va. L. Rev. 127 (2019).

[2] See id. at 129–30 nn. 4–6 (collecting sources).

[3] Id. at 147–64.

[4] Ryan Calo, Commuting to Mars: A Response to Professors Abraham & Rabin, 105 Va. L. Rev. Online 84, 84 (2019).

[5] Id. at 86.

[6] Id. at 84.

[7] Abraham & Rabin, supra note 1, at 139–45.

[8] An alleged braking failure causing injury, for example, might very well raise issues of joint responsibility of the software and hardware systems.

[9] Abraham & Rabin, supra note 1, at 132.

[10] This is likely to be a relatively objective determination of which entity has dominant responsibility for manufacture of the vehicle.

[11] Calo, supra note 4, at 87.

[12] Id. at 87.

[13] Id.

[14] Id. at 88.

[15] For discussion, see Peter H. Schuck, Tort Reform, Kiwi Style, 27 Yale L. & Pol’y Rev. 187 (2008).

[16] 42 U.S.C. §§ 300aa-1–34 (2012).

[17] 49 U.S.C. § 40101 (2012).

[18] Fla. Stat. Ann. §§ 766.301–16 (West 2018).

[19] Va. Code. Ann. §§ 38.2-5000–21 (West 2018).

[20] See, e.g., Robert L. Rabin, The September 11th Victim Compensation Fund: A Circum­scribed Response or an Auspicious Model, 53 DePaul L. Rev. 769 (2003).

Commuting to Mars: A Response to Professors Abraham and Rabin

As Yogi Berra once said, it is difficult to make predictions, especially about the future. In Automated Vehicles and Manufacturer Responsibility for Accidents: A New Legal Regime for a New Era, Professors Kenneth Abraham and Robert Rabin propose a detailed system for addressing injuries caused by driverless cars.[1] The system strikes me as sensible and well thought out given how we use cars today. But if our relationship to vehicles continues to shift with the technology, then the solution on offer has the potential to unravel.

The remarks that follow are less about the particular wisdom of manufacturer enterprise responsibility (MER) for driverless cars, and more about the limits of legal scholarship in grappling with unfolding technologic change. The contingency of technology and its social impacts caution against sweeping interventions. And the role of law and technology scholarship—as opposed to legal scholarship that touches upon technology—is arguably to recognize the unique challenges that arise at this intersection.

I.

Driverless cars are having a moment. It is not their first. In the 1990s, the Department of Transportation (DOT) became very invested in the prospect of automated vehicles for many of the same reasons that Professors Abraham and Rabin cite. The agency wrote lengthy reports on the technology and even funded an ambitious demonstration, which took place in California in 1997 to great acclaim.[2] The event garnered unprecedented media attention and popularized a term, “Intelligent Transportation Systems,” that Professors Abraham and Rabin never use, and that you have probably never even heard.[3]

Thirty years ago, the DOT assumed that the intelligence behind automated vehicles would arise from the infrastructure—street smarts, as it were. The cars of the future (i.e., of today) were to ride upon virtual rails embedded in highways and roads. Automated vehicles would avoid collision by monitoring one another, but primarily they would interact with an augmented transportation environment.

This configuration did not come to pass. If it had, the legal structures Professors Abraham and Rabin propose—responsive as they are to the complex, sometimes inscrutable design decisions made by individual manufacturers—would be of limited utility. What occurred instead is that innovations in sensing technology and machine learning in the wake of the Defense Advanced Research Projects Agency (DARPA) Grand Challenge in Nevada shepherded in an era of driverless cars with good enough sensors and processors to navigate our streets without coordination or assistance.[4]

Professors Abraham and Rabin aim their sensible intervention at the contemporary model of a driverless car and the “radically new world of auto accidents” it portends.[5] On their view, which is widely shared by government and industry, we should expect more and more vehicles on the road that are capable of driving without human intervention. At some point these vehicles will reach a critical mass—say, twenty-five percent of all registered vehicles[6]—at which time the recommendation is to pass sweeping national legislation that preempts state regulations and common law and establishes primary and exclusive liability for bodily injury in manufactures through a mandatory fund.[7]

The authors assume that driverless cars will continue to operate roughly as they do in prototype. I see this as a solid assumption about the technology. From what I know of the state of driverless car technology, and particularly given the enormous investments by industry in sensors and machine learning, I would be surprised if the basic approach to automating vehicles were to shift again dramatically in the near term.

I would be equally surprised if Americans retained anything like their present relationship to cars.

It is tempting to understand driver automation as simply the end point of a continuum, a mental model that the five “levels” developed by the Society of Automotive Engineers reinforces.[8] In actuality, the prospect of vehicles that do not require humans to drive them represents a qualitatively distinct affordance. Think of how different cities would look if parking downtown were unnecessary.[9] Imagine the variations in vehicle design that the absence of steering wheels, pedals, or even windshields will support. Consider how a vehicle that could safely drop your child off at school would affect your commute or the shape of your school district.

Indeed, traditional automotive engineers are not driving the present revolution. The leaders in the field of automated vehicles are technology companies. Driverless car pioneer Waymo is a spinoff of Google, which of course provides free digital services on an advertising model. Its nearest rival is Uber, a ride-sharing app that delivers transportation on demand. These companies are not interested in selling cars to individuals—they invest billions in automation because of the prospect of a limitless, exquisitely coordinated reservoir of robots capable of moving people around.

The prospect that widespread vehicle autonomy will dramatically alter the way humans get around has consequences, including for the proposal Professors Abraham and Rabin lay out in careful detail. As Professors Abraham and Rabin remark in passing, “private vehicle ownership may go the way of the horse-and-buggy.”[10] Nevertheless, the liability system on offer repeatedly assumes that individuals will own and insure their own cars. For example, MER would exclude property damage on the apparent assumption that highly automated vehicle owners “still will likely purchase conventional auto insurance.”[11]

When I conceive of even the immediate future of driverless vehicles, I do not think of a trip to the Volkswagen dealership to trade in my level three for a shiny new level four. I think of diversified fleets of automated vehicles owned by the companies that made them, or by large civic units such as cities, and deployed as a transportation resource in the near term. The relationship between an injured consumer and a private or public service, meanwhile, raises distinct considerations from traditional products liability. And while Uber and Volkswagen are each capable of spreading and avoiding costs, the incentive structure of an app-based technology company that both owns and operates its vehicles differs rather markedly from that of a car manufacturer that sells vehicles to people.

I don’t have a crystal ball, any more than the authors. Imagine that neither I nor Professors Abraham and Rabin have correctly identified the future relationship of most Americans to vehicles or the timescale upon which change will occur. The very prospect that dramatically distinct modalities of transportation could arise from the ability of vehicles to drive themselves seems to caution against a preemptive, administratively intense solution that forbids state legislatures or courts from experimentation. Not even the apparent inspiration for MER—workers compensation—represents federal policy; workers comp is rather a creature of the state that can vary accordingly. Said another way, the authors’ proposal is certain; the future is not.

II.

The puzzle of how to deal with the contingency of technology and its social impacts is not limited to driverless cars, but endemic to law and technology scholarship. Personally I doubt Professors Abraham and Rabin—each renowned scholars of civil liability—identify themselves as working in “law and technology” as such. I imagine that for the authors, the ascendance of automated vehicles is just a fact about the world like any other, as the progress of technology often is.[12] In my experience, however, reasoning about technological change sometimes requires special care.

Take the concept of the “driverless car.” The underlying innovations that make driverless cars possible are, again, the introduction of new sensors (especially lidar) and improvements in techniques of machine learning that help computers recognize and react to patterns. These innovations introduce new human affordances, in the sense of additional capabilities to interact with our environment.[13] But even assuming the end goal is safely moving people about, there is nothing inevitable about combining these constituent technologies in a traditional car. That decision flows from a constellation of choices dating back to the concerted effort of the automotive industry to promote individual car ownership, and the attendant—and, some allege, purposive—decimation of public transportation.[14]

If we disaggregate the innovation of more accurate sensors and better machine learning from the construct of a driverless car, then far broader legal ramifications seem to follow. Consider Professors Abraham and Rabin’s key argument around why MER is necessary: neither federal agencies nor courts and juries possess the expertise to unpack the “esoteric, algorithm-based design differences” between highly automated vehicles.[15] Surely this concern extends well beyond driverless cars to the very wide array of robotics and cyber-physical systems being marketed and developed today.[16] The reader would be forgiven for wondering what intellectual foundation there could be to arguing for an elaborate and expensive MER regime for vehicles but nothing else.

My own view—which I am developing in connection to a larger project on law and technology—is that any legal scholarship that interacts with physical and digital artifacts would do well to state and defend a series of assumptions. Legal scholarship in general tends not to dwell on questions of methodology. I understand that Professors Abraham and Rabin expect MER to be evaluated on the basis of efficiency and cost-benefit analysis because I teach torts and I recognize the language of “optimal,” “adverse selection,” and “transaction costs.” But law and technology scholarship in particular would benefit from reflecting on a series of choices that are today largely implicit.

One set of choices involves the methods and goals of the author. Much law and technology literature follows Professor Rabin’s former colleague Lawrence Lessig in understanding new technology as revealing “[l]atent ambiguities,” or gaps in the law that jurists must now resolve.[17] Scholarship in this mold is at once progressive, in that it takes technological progress as inevitable, and conservative, in that it understands the role of law as restoring the status quo ex ante in light of a disruption. There are alternatives to this approach, ranging from purely descriptive research that helps provide ground truth, to normative projects that understand new technology as an invitation to rethink what constitute realistic societal goals.

The response you are reading concerns another choice: What is the scope of the technology under examination? Relatedly, what assumptions are the authors making around the trajectory of the technology or its social impact?

As a longtime science fiction fan, I remember coming across the early days of the genre depicting marvelous progress in technology even as social norms somehow remained constant—1950s science fiction classics that invite the viewer to picture a world in which businessmen routinely commute to Mars on aircraft piloted by white men and serviced by stewardesses in short skirts. The reality is far more complex. Technological change occurs against a backdrop of social, cultural, and economic forces that in turn shape the trajectory of the technology itself.

A wide variety of factors suggest that we may be on the cusp of a sea change in transportation. The very distinctions between manufacturer, owner, and consumers seem likely to collapse. The trouble with technology—and hence law and technology scholarship—is that truly novel affordances tend to invite reexamination of how we live. Legal scholarship must acknowledge this prospect or risk being its casualty.

 

 


[1] Kenneth S. Abraham & Robert L. Rabin, Automated Vehicles and Manufacturer Respon­sibility for Accidents: A New Legal Regime for a New Era, 105 Va. L. Rev. 127 (2019).

[2] For a first-hand description, see Chuck Thorpe et al., The 1997 Automated Highway Free Agent Demonstration, 1998 IEEE 496–501.

[3] Berkeley California PATH, National Automated Highway Systems Consortium (2019), [https://perma.cc/PV68-GR49] (last visited Feb. 21, 2019) (“Demo ’97 generated an unprece­dented level of media attention for Intelligent Transportation Systems, and we have made no attempt to capture the media aspects of that event here.”).

[4] See John Markoff, Machines of Loving Grace: The Quest for Common Ground Between Humans and Robots 23, 28–29, 36 (2015) (discussing advances in machines in the wake of the DARPA Grand Challenge).

[5] Abraham & Rabin, supra note 1, at 128–29.

[6] Id. at 132.

[7] See id. at 148–49, 151–52.

[8] The authors describe and embrace the levels in the Introduction. Id. at 129–31.

[9] See Alan Ohnsman, The End Of Parking Lots As We Know Them: Designing For A Driverless Future, Forbes (May 18, 2018, 11:31 AM), [https://perma.cc/FSJ5-A34J]; Tech Policy Lab, Driverless Seattle: How Cities Can Prepare for Automated Vehicles (Mar. 1, 2017), [https://perma.cc/M7GN-ZMUC].

[10] Abraham & Rabin, supra note 1, at 130.

[11] Id. at 151–55.

[12] Thus, for example, the Washington Supreme Court found no negligence on the part of the county for failing to build guardrails in 1928 capable of stopping a horse-drawn cart but not a car. Davison v. Snohomish Cty., 270 P.2d 422, 423 (Wash. 1928). That same court would later require a jury to determine whether a railway company was negligent forty years later for failing to protect against a similar accident on the theory that materials had become stronger and cheaper. Bartlett v. N. Pac. Ry. Co., 447 P.2d 735, 737 (Wash. 1968).

[13] For a discussion of affordances, see Ryan Calo, Can Americans Resist Surveillance?, 83 U. Chi. L. Rev. 23, 26–30 (2016).

[14] See, e.g., Robert C. Fellmeth, Politics of Land: Ralph Nader’s Study Group Report on Land Use in California 406, 415 (1973); see also Kate Crawford & Ryan Calo, Comment, There Is a Blind Spot in AI Research, 538 Nature 311, 311–313 (2016) (discussing how the trolley problem obscures the ways that investment in autonomous driving perpetuates prioritization of private cars over public transport). 

[15] Abraham & Rabin, supra note 1, at 142–44. The Toyota sudden acceleration scandal of 2011 provides an excellent example. Congress instructed the DOT to determine whether the reported propensity of Toyotas suddenly to accelerate was the product of a glitch in the software. The DOT lacked the requisite expertise to answer this question and wound up having to ask NASA to take a break from placing robots on Mars to look at a Toyota for them. It took NASA four months, but they eventually cleared Toyota’s software. See Ryan Calo, The Case for a Federal Robotics Commission, Brookings Inst. (Sept. 15, 2014), [https://perma.cc/4LS2-T7HM].

[16] These include drones, delivery carts, surgical robots, and personal and service robots.

[17] Lawrence Lessig, Code and Other Laws of Cyberspace 22 (1999).