What’s Wrong with Sentencing Equality? Sentencing Legality: A Response to Professors Bierschbach & Bibas

In 2005, I was a public defender in Bronx County, New York. Contemplating a transition to academia, I developed an idea for an article about plea-bargaining and innocence.[1] Early on, I came across a tremendously helpful paper, written by Professor Stephanos Bibas.[2] Several months later, I began a teaching fellowship. On the first day, I was pleased to find Bibas’s name on the office door next to mine. Unfortunately, Bibas had already left for another institution. Our paths seemed destined not to cross. Still, I took a chance and emailed him. Bibas responded with warm words and constructive advice. Over the next decade, our relationship would become one of the most valuable of my professional career. His generosity is unparalleled, and my scholarship is demonstrably better for it. Sometimes we disagree, though perhaps less so recently (which only speaks to the great influence he has had on my thinking).

Coincidentally, I knew Professor Rick Bierschbach even before I left criminal practice. We were acquaintances—at opposite ends of a large circle of thirty-something lawyers. Rick’s reputation preceded him. He was (and is) a mensch.[3] And, true to his kind nature, he has always been available to lend an ear and to offer useful feedback.

What is the point of these brief testimonials? It is, of course, a law review convention to begin a response with kind words for the article’s authors. But that is not my principal aim. By this genuine and personal expression of affection for two profoundly decent individuals, I hope to show the power of narrative—the capacity for detail to reach comparatively more than form. The entrenched form is merely to celebrate the authors’ professional qualifications and achievements. But my narrative aspires to reach something deeper and richer. The evaluation of an academic’s worth (or lack thereof) entails much more than a recitation of her accomplishments. Similarly, the evaluation of an offender’s blameworthiness (or lack thereof) entails much more than legal and factual guilt. No single set of criteria—promulgated ex ante—is competent to tell the complete story in all its intricacies.

Bierschbach and Bibas understand this, of course. Indeed, it is a central premise of their remarkable article, What’s Wrong with Sentencing Equality? They explain that positive sentencing law has unduly prioritized sentencing “math” over other relevant (indeed, potentially more relevant) moral and prudential considerations.[4] Mandatory rules operate to sort offenders into predetermined boxes and types, typically defined by criminal records and crimes of conviction.[5] Like outcomes are thereafter imposed for each offender of every broad type.

The authors trace the source of the prevailing approach to the equality principle—or, rather, to our dominant conception of it. But I am not so sure. The first-order question is why our criminal justice system has settled upon such a formalistic conception of equality. The unanswered question is what makes sentencing math so attractive, as compared to some alternative qualitative approach to equality that might accommodate more detail. The answer to that question lies with another contested principle—the legality principle, which Professor Herbert Packer famously termed “the first principle of criminal law.”[6] The root of what is wrong with sentencing equality arises from our positive conception of this first principle, not from our positive conception of equality itself. Our fetish for formal legality is what drives our commitment to formal equality.[7] But equality qua equality is tangential, at best.

I. Three Conceptions of Equality

Bierschbach and Bibas recognize that there may be more than one viable conception of equality[8] They distinguish between our positive (and problematic) substantive conception, which aims to guarantee equal results, defined formally; and a procedural conception, which aims to guarantee equal opportunities to argue for defendant-favorable results.[9] They use the descriptor “outcomes-oriented” to describe the prevailing substantive approach, and they discuss its underappreciated tradeoffs.[10] Likewise, they defend alternative procedural approaches to equality (even random processes, like lotteries and dice rolls) as consistent with what John Rawls called “pure procedural justice.”[11]

Nevertheless, they fail to appreciate that there are, in fact, two very different strands of “outcomes-oriented” equality. There is a formal strand and an equitable strand. Pursuant to the equitable strand, there is no necessary tradeoff between individualization and equality. To the contrary, individualization is the means by which equitable equality is achieved. As I have explained elsewhere:

A justice system that admits equitable considerations is premised on the fact that legally identical cases should sometimes be handled differently for normative reasons. This does not mean, however, that equitable [variation] deviates unduly from a defensible notion of equality. . . . [A] contextualized approach to criminal justice necessarily demands more than just a rigid application of legal rules pursuant to formal designations. It demands an evaluation of relative blameworthiness to ensure that equitably distinct cases are recognized as such, even if those cases happen to be legally identical under insufficiently discriminating statutes.[12]

With respect to both the formal and equitable strands of equality, case outcomes provide the relevant reference points. In this way, both approaches remain substantive. The difference is only whether these outcomes are determined to be equitably or formally distinct or alike.

The reason for the misconception—for describing equitable equality as procedural equality—is the pivotal role that narrative plays in “equitable judgment.”[13] Narrative is, of course, a procedural endeavor. But the practice is only a means to the decisive end—a means “to look into things more deeply, to see whether we may have missed some unusual impediment that deformed the process of character formation.”[14] It is only once we have attended to the complete “narrative history” that we can determine whether a given penalty really fits the particular crime—or whether the prescribed sentence, instead, has failed to account for some “unusual hardship or inequality.”[15] On this reading, the stories we tell shape the sentences we impose. We contrast one story with the next to realize whether we have adequately grasped the differences between them.[16]

Thus, there are (at least[17]) three conceptions of equality: a procedural conception that promises like opportunities to argue; a substantive equitable conception that promises like normative results; and a substantive formal conception that promises like legalistic results. Results matter only with respect to the two substantive conceptions. But each substantive conception entails a radically different method by which to discover and ultimately compare blameworthiness.

The preceding is, to some degree, no more than a small taxonomical quibble. But I think it necessary to define our terms correctly in order to discern properly why the criminal justice system is so allergic to equitable equality. Bierschbach and Bibas do not make clear enough that the problem with positive sentencing law is not its focus on outcomes, but rather its fixation with law—a fixation that has produced results that are more obviously ordered than equal.

II. What’s Exceptional with Criminal Justice?

Sentencing was once different. Sentencing law “traditionally permitted the story of the defendant’s character-formation to come before the judge or jury in all its narrative complexity . . . .”[18] Over time, however, determinate sentencing regimes have reduced or eliminated the judge’s opportunities for “sympathetic assessment” and “merciful mitigation”—and, for that matter, for penalty enhancements for particularly bad actors and heinous acts.[19] Ironically, our most severe punishment—the death penalty—describes the one constitutional context in which the practice of narrative has continued to hold sway.[20]

What changed? Bierschbach and Bibas take as given the conventional wisdom that mandatory sentencing regimes developed as compromises between progressives (intent on reining in racial, ethnic, and class discrimination) and conservatives (intent on reining in lenient judges).[21] But the conventional wisdom is incomplete. It provides only an explanation for why both sides prioritized equality over other principles and values, but it does not account for why they settled on a formal conception of substantive equality. The answer to that question depends on an older trend.

Going back to the Enlightenment, political theorists have championed the legality principle as an “important prophylaxis against the arbitrary and abusive exercise of discretion in the enforcement of the penal law.”[22] The classical liberal view is that well-defined rules are the best means to achieve legality’s objectives—that, to the extent possible, the terms of criminal culpability and punishment must remain prospective and precise.[23] And that view gained greater currency in response to the atrocities committed by last century’s totalitarian powers.[24] Thus, even as the rest of the law witnessed a “revolt against formalism,” the law of crime—including sentencing law—grew more rule-bound.[25] This is the idea behind “the rule of law as a law of rules”—an idea grounded in legal formalism.[26] And it is this same impulse that also informs our formal conception of equality and, by extension, our rule-bound sentencing law.

The authors seem genuinely curious as to why we speak pejoratively about sentencing “disparities,” while we have elsewhere defended variability as the acceptable (or even virtuous) byproduct of “localism,” “pluralism,” or “laboratories of democracy.”[27] But there is no mystery. The “law of crime” is thought exceptional precisely because criminal justice is exceptionally harsh and stigmatic.[28] The coercion of conviction and sentence carries with it a corresponding “especial need for certainty,” which is considered essential to prevent liberal punishment from slipping into rank oppression.[29] Ultimately, then, it is our prevailing notion of the rule of law that is doing the bulk of the work. Indeed, Professor Peter Westen has observed that there is always some equality-independent principle—some alternative “moral standard”—that is doing the bulk of the work:

Equality is an empty vessel with no substantive moral content of its own. Without moral standards, equality remains meaningless, a formula that can have nothing to say about how we should act. . . . 

              . . . . 

Relationships of equality (and inequality) are derivative, secondary relationships; they are logically posterior, not anterior . . . . To say that two persons are the same in a certain respect is to presuppose . . . a prescribed standard for treating them . . . . Before such a rule is established, no standard of comparison exists.”[30]

Bierschbach and Bibas commit a category error. They mistake the triumph of a formal conception of legality with the triumph of a formal conception of equality. In fact, our obsession is not with equal outcomes as much as highly predictable and ordered outcomes. This is what the authors do not quite grasp. Consider this observation: “The stale sentencing debate[] of . . . rules versus standards needs to stop treating equality as if it were a single concept.”[31] But the rules-standards debate is neither stale nor peripheral. To the contrary, our false impression that equality is a single concept is a direct byproduct of our fidelity to rules. Equality comes in different shapes and sizes, but the dominant conception of legality is built to perceive just one—a breed of equality born of rules. When the authors celebrate a “more elastic approach[]” to sentencing equality, they are only pushing a “more elastic approach[]” to legality.[32] The equality question is a mere echo of the legality debate.

III. What’s Right (and Natural) About Sentencing Equity?

In the space provided, I cannot possibly defend thoroughly the ambitious claim that an “elastic approach” to legality is nonetheless consistent with the rule of law. Elsewhere, I do more to support this bold proposition.[33] I have argued even that a softer conception of legality might provide better protection against rough punishment, at least in some contexts.[34] To be sure, there are limits to any workable and defensible equitable approach, as even committed moral particularists have recognized.[35] No system is competent to attend to every relevant detail.[36] Legal standards set the outer boundaries. And, because resources are finite, sentencing proceedings can accommodate only so much scrutiny. But even within these practical parameters, an evaluative system necessarily has the capacity to perceive more than a mechanistic system. The process is imperfect, but not obviously arbitrary.[37]

The misapprehension—that equitable evaluation is incompatible with legality—is based upon the tendency of particularistic methodologies to reveal unwelcome disparities. But there is a difference in kind between creating a disparity and exposing what was always there. Formal legality paves over incongruence; its methods are mechanistic, facile, and somewhat fictive. Equitable legality engages incongruence; its methods are evaluative, complex, and relatively honest. Formal legality promotes a conception of equality that is predictable but thin. Equitable legality promotes a conception of equality that is indeterminate but thick. When it comes to the equitable approach, what we construe to be cacophony may just be consistency by another name—succinctly, individualization in the service of a thoroughgoing qualitative comparison. According to Professors Martha Nussbaum and Dan Kahan, “It’s when the law falsely denies its evaluative underpinnings that it is most likely to be incoherent and inconsistent; it is when the law refuses to take responsibility for its most contentious choices that its decision makers are spared the need to be principled . . . .”[38]

There is, after all, nothing inherently equality-enhancing about a rule that provides: sell X grams of heroin; receive Z years in prison. To the contrary, commentators have long observed that “sentencing math” promotes inconsistency by failing to account meaningfully for the offender’s genuine role in the offense.[39] Little fish are treated like big fish, and big fish trade information for undeserved cooperation pleas.[40] One response is that prosecutors retain the charging and bargaining discretion not only to use over-inclusive sentencing rules as threats, but also to correct for these rules’ overreach. Thus, they may choose not to treat little fish like big fish, even if the law ostensibly commands that they do so. Put differently, they may pursue individualized “substantive justice,” even (or especially) within mandatory regimes.[41]

But this prospect is hardly comforting. As Bierschbach and Bibas recognize, even if prosecutors “have the perspective and power to balance individual blameworthiness against systemic demands,” they are also subject to “incentives to clear cases quickly,” as well as other institutional and cognitive biases that may undercut their willingness (or even their ability) to exercise equitable discretion consistently, fairly, and effectively.[42] The problem is not only that the prosecutor is a professional, but also that she is partial. Here, the authors generously reference my scholarship to support the proposition that prosecutorial “decisions often turn on legalistic habits of charging and plea bargaining.”[43] But I am equally troubled (if not more so) by the manner in which prosecutors may indulge their extra-legalistic habits—their “‘nonlegal impetus’” to pursue their own vested interests and their own idiosyncratic notions of moral or prudential blameworthiness.[44]

If nothing else, the scope of prosecutorial power reveals a profound truth about almost any purportedly mandatory rule. It is destined, by some degree, to fail. The discretion we stamp out at one stage reappears at another. The authority we strip from one stakeholder works its way to another.[45] Like water through a weak dike, discretion finds the cracks—and there are always cracks. With this in mind, it makes little sense to construct a sentencing system that serves to delegate equitable authority to the least transparent and most biased parties—specifically, the prosecutors who control the pivotal decisions over whether to file mandatory charges (and whether to negotiate around them, thereafter).

I do not mean to suggest that the authors fail to appreciate this concern. To the contrary, they note, “[s]ome of the blameworthiness factors . . . . inform low-visibility but influential decisions by . . . prosecutors . . . to decline or divert charges, to plea bargain, and to strike cooperation deals, among other things. But the hydraulic pressures to dispose of cases quickly make these decisions invisible, unchecked, unaccountable, and highly variable.”[46] Yet the inevitability of discretion reveals something more profound still. Discretion is natural, whereas rule-bound reasoning is artificial. At best, rule-bound reasoning is infantile and small-minded.[47] The mature mind strives to understand things more deeply.[48] The criminal justice system is a human system, and no human system is prepared to dispense with context wholesale. This, then, seems to be what Bierschbach and Bibas mean when they write that “laymen care about a good deal more” than rigid sentencing rules.[49] Laymen also care about motive, social circumstance, and character (and also, for that matter, innumerable other moral and prudential questions and considerations).

Don’t get me wrong. As between a system stripped free of equity and a system that assigns equitable discretion exclusively to the executive, I prefer the latter—but only because one is impossible and even less desirable than the other. But neither is all that attractive. One of Bibas’s most important contributions is his brilliant book, The Machinery of Criminal Justice.[50] He hit upon certain fundamental realities—that the “machinery of criminal justice” is the province of neither sovereign prerogative nor the unbending rule.[51] In truth, liberal criminal justice is not machinery at all.

Conclusion

A mandatory sentence is like a store-bought greeting card. It strives to express a moral sentiment. But, except by rough fit, it cannot manage a genuine connection. It is just an abstract product of what typical people typically feel about typical groups. Preset categories are all that describe who should be considered similarly situated to whom. The core problem, however, is not that the mass-produced sentence (or, for that matter, the mass-produced greeting card) says the same things to everyone, but rather that it says empty things to everyone. The mandatory sentence is shallow.

Bierschbach and Bibas still need to identify the source of equality’s shallowness, as it applies to positive law. The authors’ point of attack is a particular approach to the principle. But by giving such primacy to the dominant conception of equality, they unintentionally buy into it. The real problem is legality, as conventionally formulated and expressed.

 


[1]Josh Bowers, Punishing the Innocent, 156 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1117, 1117 (2008).

[2]Stephanos Bibas, Bringing Moral Values into a Flawed Plea-Bargaining System, 88 Cornell L. Rev. 1425 (2003).

[3]“Mensch” is the Yiddish word for a good person. See Mensch, Dictionary.com, http://www.dictionary.com/browse/mensch?s=t [https://perma.cc/9W9M-C3CK].

[4]Richard A. Bierschbach & Stephanos Bibas, What’s Wrong with Sentencing Equality? 102 Va. L. Rev. 1447, 1455, 1465 (2016) (“Where moral disagreement was endemic, math supplanted morality.”).

[5]Josh Bowers, Legal Guilt, Normative Innocence, and the Equitable Decision Not to Prosecute, 110 Colum. L. Rev. 1655, 1688–92 (2010) [hereinafter Bowers, Legal Guilt]; see also Wayne A. Logan, Proportionality and Punishment: Imposing Life Without Parole on Juveniles, 33 Wake Forest L. Rev. 681, 703 (1998) (“Crime is now typically conceived solely in terms of the relative seriousness of a given offense, to the exclusion of offender culpability.”).

[6]Herbert L. Packer, The Limits of the Criminal Sanction 79–80 (1968).

[7]On our overly formal conception of the legality principle, see Josh Bowers, Probable Cause, Constitutional Reasonableness, and the Unrecognized Point of a “Pointless Indignity”, 66 Stan. L. Rev. 987, 996–98 (2014) [hereinafter Bowers, Pointless Indignity]; Josh Bowers, Legality & Rough Justice 6–7 (May 30, 2014) (unpublished manuscript) (on file with author); Josh Bowers, Understanding the Police 1 (Oct. 5, 2016) [hereinafter Bowers, Understanding the Police] (unpublished manuscript) (on file with author).

[8]Bierschbach & Bibas, supra note 4, at 1492 (observing that “many alternative conceptions of sentencing equality” exist); cf. Peter Westen, The Empty Idea of Equality, 95 Harv. L. Rev. 537, 537 (1982) (tracing the endurance of the principle to its ability to shift shape).

[9]Bierschbach & Bibas, supra note 4, at 1447.

[10]Id. at 1456–57 (“[O]ur main goal is to show how sentencing equality, as it has come to be conventionally understood in outcomes-oriented terms, interacts with the institutional structure and goals of punishment, and how exposing that interaction complicates the tradeoffs that inhere in sentencing design.”).

[11]John Rawls, A Theory of Justice 75 (rev. ed. 1999) (defining “pure procedural justice” as a “fair procedure” that produces a result that is “likewise correct or fair, whatever it is, provided that the procedure has been properly followed”); see Bowers, Legal Guilt, supra note 5, at 1677 (“[T]here is no persuasive reason why equal treatment must be measured according to substantive outcomes only.”); Vincent Chiao, Ex Ante Fairness in Criminal Law and Procedure, 15 New Crim. L. Rev. 277 (2012).

[12]Bowers, Legal Guilt, supra note 5, at 1673–74; Logan, supra note 5, at 703 n.108 (“All defendants are not alike, just as all crimes, even if given the same label, are not identical.” (internal quotation marks and citation omitted)).

[13]Martha C. Nussbaum, Equity and Mercy, 22 Phil. & Pub. Aff. 83, 85–86, 92 (1993) (defining “equitable judgment” as “judgment that attends to the particulars,” and as “a gentle art of particular perception, a temper of mind that refuses to demand retribution without understanding the whole story”). My conception of equitable judgment is consistent with what Aristotle called epieikeia or “fair-mindedness.” Lawrence B. Solum, Virtue Jurisprudence: A Virtue-Centered Theory of Judging, 34 Metaphilosophy 178, 205 (2003).

[14]Dan M. Kahan & Martha C. Nussbaum, Two Conceptions of Emotion in Criminal Law, 96 Colum. L. Rev. 269, 368–70 (1996) (comparing mechanistic and evaluative approaches).

[15]Id. In any event, even our conventional legalistic conception of equality depends upon procedural methods. Here, the means consist of the conventional (and relatively technical) deconstructive craft of legal analysis, as opposed to the constructive craft of narrative. Bowers, Legal Guilt, supra note 5, at 1690–91 (describing what it means to think and reason like a lawyer).

[16]Packer, supra note 6, at 88 (“It is not enough to say: this man goes to jail because he did something bad. There is obligation to relate the particular bad thing that this man did to other bad things that have been created as criminal in the past.”).

[17]Cf. infra note 30 and accompanying text (discussing Peter Westen’s view that equality is secondary to—and defined by—other enumerable moral principles).

[18]Kahan & Nussbaum, supra note 14, at 367; see also Bierschbach & Bibas, supra note 4, at 1473 (“[T]he criminal justice system once did and could again make a point of promoting remorse, apology, forgiveness, and reconciliation . . . . about treating victims and offenders with dignity and respect . . . . But these considerations . . . . require context-specific judgments of real human beings . . . .” (footnote omitted)).

[19]Kahan & Nussbaum, supra note 14, at 367.

[20]Enmund v. Florida, 458 U.S. 782, 801 (1982) (“[P]unishment must be tailored to . . . personal responsibility and moral guilt.”); Lockett v. Ohio, 438 U.S. 586, 604 (1978) (holding that the capital sentencing jury is entitled to consider “as a mitigating factor, any aspect of a defendant’s character or record and any of the circumstances of the offense that the defendant proffers as a basis for a sentence less than death”); see Josh Bowers, Mandatory Life and the Death of Equitable Discretion, in Life Without Parole: America’s New Death Penalty? 25, 25 (Charles J. Ogletree Jr. & Austin Sarat eds., 2012) [hereinafter Bowers, Mandatory Life].

[21]Bierschbach & Bibas, supra note 4, at 1459; see Michael Tonry, Sentencing Matters 6, 9, 147 (1996). I do not reject the conventional story entirely. Indeed, I have even articulated it previously. Josh Bowers, Contraindicated Drug Courts, 55 UCLA L. Rev. 783, 825 (2008) (“Stakeholders of varied political stripes came together to counteract what some saw as racist inequities in sentencing and what others saw as overly lenient discretionary sentencing.”); Bowers, Mandatory Life, supra note 20, at 30 (“Left-liberals saw determinate sentencing to be an antidote to racial and economic inequalities in discretionary sentencing. Law-and-order conservatives saw determinate sentencing to be an antidote to lenient liberal judges.” (footnote omitted)).

[22]Richard J. Bonnie et al., Criminal Law 81 (3d ed. 2010); John Calvin Jeffries, Jr., Legality, Vagueness, and the Construction of Penal Statutes, 71 Va. L. Rev. 189, 201, 212 (1985) (“The rule of law signifies the constraint of arbitrariness in the exercise of government power.”).

[23]Christine Sypnowich, Utopia and the Rule of Law in Recrafting the Rule of Law: The Limits of Legal Order 178, 179–80 (David Dyzenhaus ed., 1999) (“[T]he rule of law . . . refer[s] to the idea that law should meet certain procedural requirements so that the individual is enabled to obey it. . . . [It must] be relatively certain, clearly expressed, open, . . . adequately publicised . . . . [and] prospective . . . . The practical effect . . . is to set limits to the discretion of legislators, administrators, judges and the police.”).

[24]Bonnie et al., supra note 22, at 83 (“Would a Puritan theocracy or an Islamic state or a Marxist dictatorship have a comparable commitment to protecting . . . . the principle of legality as a fundamental ideal of the penal law dictated by liberal democracy and its underlying assumptions about the relation of the state to individual citizens?”); cf. Packer, supra note 6, at 86–87 (describing development of the legality principle and concluding that “after centuries of retrospective law-making by judges, . . . . the process of judicial law-making in the criminal field has . . . come to a halt” (emphasis omitted)).

[25]Louis Michael Seidman, Points of Intersection: Discontinuities at the Junction of Criminal Law and the Regulatory State, 7 J. Contemp. Legal Issues 97, 98, 101, 103 (1996) (“[A]lthough realism’s lessons for criminal law seem obvious, formalism continues to dominate criminal jurisprudence.”).

[26]Jeffries, supra note 22, at 212 (describing the “quite conventional” prevailing conception of the rule of law and the principle of legality); Antonin Scalia, Essay, The Rule of Law as a Law of Rules, 56 U. Chi. L. Rev. 1175 (1989). According to Professor John Jeffries: “[T]he agencies of official coercion should, to the extent feasible, be guided by rules” as a means to promote “regularity and evenhandedness in the administration of justice and accountability in the use of government power.” Jeffries, supra note 22, at 201, 212 (explaining that “appeals to the ‘rule of law,’” as they apply to the penal law tend to entail “the resort to legal formalism as a constraint against unbridled discretion”); Bowers, Pointless Indignity, supra note 7, at 989–98 (examining and critiquing the prevailing perspective); Bowers, Understanding the Police, supra note 7, at 1 (same).

[27]Bierschbach & Bibas, supra note 4, at 1450–51, 1489 (“One might even argue that the arguments and observations of Gerken, Leib, and Schragger should have special purchase at sentencing, with its lack of easy policy answers, difficult moral tradeoffs, and inextricable connection to community norms.”); see also id. at 1487 (“The assumption in all of this is that punishment should not turn on local views.”); id at 1490–91, 1495 (arguing that “normative variation” may be “a virtue, not a vice”).

[28]Egon Bittner, The Police on Skid-Row: A Study of Peace Keeping, 32 Am. Sociological Rev. 699, 700 (1967) (“[C]rime belongs wholly to the law, and its treatment is exhaustively based on considerations of legality . . . .”); Seidman, supra note 25, at 97.

[29]Stephen R. Perry, Judicial Obligation, Precedent, and the Common Law, 7 Oxford J. Legal Stud. 215, 256 (1987); see also H.L.A. Hart, Legal Responsibility and Excuses, in Punishment and Responsibility 28, 44–47 (1968) (comparing certainty in criminal punishment to certainty in private law); Kenneth I. Winston, On Treating Like Cases Alike, 62 Calif. L. Rev. 1, 37 (1974) (discussing criminal law’s long tradition of “strict adherence to rules”); cf. Sherry F. Colb, Freedom from Incarceration: Why is This Right Different from All Other Rights?, 69 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 781, 821 (1994) (explaining that criminal justice is different in kind from other forms of legal regulation and that “liberty from confinement cannot be relegated to the status of unprotected aspects of daily life”).

[30]Westen, supra note 8, at 545, 547–48 (footnotes omitted).

[31]Bierschbach & Bibas, supra note 4, at 1520 (emphasis added).

[32]Id at 1514.

[33]Bowers, Pointless Indignity, supra note 7, at 1030–43; Bowers, Understanding the Police, supra note 7, at 1.

[34]Specifically, I claim that equitable oversight is critical to regulating appropriately the enforcement and adjudication of low-level crimes. Bowers, Pointless Indignity, supra note 7, at 1036–37; Bowers, Understanding the Police, supra note 7, at 20.

[35]Bowers, Legal Guilt, supra note 5, at 1670 (citing sources).

[36]Id. at 1670–72; Nussbaum, supra note 13, at 93 (“[T]he ‘matter of the practical’ can be grasped only crudely by rules given in advance, and adequately only by a flexible judgment suited to the complexities of the case.”); Solum, supra note 13, at 206 (“[T]he infinite variety and complexity of particular fact situations outruns our capacity to formulate general rules.”).

[37]Kenneth Culp Davis, Discretionary Justice: A Preliminary Inquiry 21 (1969) (“[T]he conception of equity that discretion is needed as an escape from rigid rules [is] a far cry from the proposition that where law ends tyranny begins.”).

[38]Kahan & Nussbaum, supra note 14, at 274, 373–74 (noting that evaluations of normative blameworthiness “are better because they are brutally and uncompromisingly honest,” whereas “[m]echanistic doctrines . . . tend to disguise contentious moral issues”); William J. Stuntz, Unequal Justice, 121 Harv. L. Rev. 1969, 2039 (2008) (“[W]hen prosecutors have enormous discretionary power, giving other decisionmakers discretion promotes consistency, not arbitrariness. . . . [I]nstitutional competition curbs excess and abuse.”). In this vein, Professor Bill Stuntz argued that even localism is compatible with equality. Id. at 1995, 2031–33 (noting that “equality and local democracy [may] go hand in hand”).

[39]United States v. Justice, 877 F.2d 664, 666 (8th Cir. 1989) (describing federal sentencing as a “mechanical process”); Douglas A. Berman, The Virtues of Offense/Offender Distinctions, in Criminal Law Conversations 611, 615 (Paul H. Robins, Stephen P. Garvey & Kimberly Kessler Ferzan eds., 2009) (criticizing federal sentencing guidelines as “a sentencing process that [has] been drained of its humanity”); Bowers, Mandatory Life, supra note 20, at 29 (“[T]he vagaries of life outstrip ‘sentencing math’ that tends to count most that which can be counted most easily—like drug weight and monetary loss, as opposed to moral blameworthiness.” (emphasis omitted) (citing Berman, supra, at 615)); Jack B. Weinstein, Comment, A Trial Judge’s Second Impression of the Federal Sentencing Guidelines, 66 S. Cal. L. Rev. 357, 364 (1992).

[40]Daniel C. Richman, Cooperating Defendants: The Costs and Benefits of Purchasing Information from Scoundrels, 8 Fed. Sentencing Rep. 292, 292 (1996). The authors understand this, of course. They emphasize “more granular” approaches that turn on “less-quantifiable values” than determinate facts and figures, like drug weight and monetary gain. Bierschbach & Bibas, supra note 4, at 1455.

[41]Malcolm M. Feeley, The Process Is the Punishment: Handling Cases in a Lower Criminal Court xix (1979); Bowers, Legal Guilt, supra note 5, at 1708. It is well understood that determinate sentencing empowers prosecutors. Rachel E. Barkow, Institutional Design and Policing of Prosecutors: Lessons from Administrative Law, 61 Stan. L. Rev. 869, 877 (2009) (“With the prevalence of mandatory minimum laws, a prosecutor’s decision to bring or not bring charges can dictate whether a defendant receives a mandatory five-, ten-, or twenty-year term, or whether he or she is sentenced far below that floor.”); David Bjerk, Making the Crime Fit the Penalty: The Role of Prosecutorial Discretion Under Mandatory Minimum Sentencing, 48 J.L. & Econ. 591, 593–95 (2005); William J. Stuntz, Plea Bargaining and Criminal Law’s Disappearing Shadow, 117 Harv. L. Rev. 2548, 2564 (2004).

[42]Bierschbach & Bibas, supra note 4, at 1482; see also Bowers, Legal Guilt, supra note 5, at 1687 (“[P]rosecutors possess the human capacity for practical reason. But, in their professional roles, they are first and foremost legally trained institutional actors. And their position and profession may profoundly limit the degree to which they are willing and able to exercise equitable discretion—particularly in the petty cases where such discretion is most warranted.”); Bowers, Mandatory Life, supra note 20, at 36 (observing that a “‘mechanistic, impersonal, lawyerized criminal justice’ may interfere with what some have identified as an intuitive ‘deep human need’ to humanize and particularize retributive questions” (quoting Stephanos Bibas, Forgiveness in Criminal Procedure, 4 Ohio St. J. Crim. L. 347, 348 (2007))).

[43]Bierschbach & Bibas, supra note 4, at 1482 (emphasis added) (citing Bowers, Legal Guilt, supra note 5, at 1701–02).

[44]Bowers, Understanding the Police, supra note 7, at 22 (quoting Frederick Schauer, Analogy in the Supreme Court, Lozman v. City of Riviera Beach, Florida, 2013 Sup. Ct. Rev. 405, 429 (defining a “nonlegal impetus” as, inter alia, an “idiosyncratic reaction to . . . the very particular facts of the case”)).

[45]Bierschbach & Bibas, supra note 4, at 1470 (observing that individualization that is “omitted” from sentencing “show[s] up elsewhere in the system”); Bowers, Legal Guilt, supra note 5, at 1687 n.146 (“[D]iscretion is a hydraulic force. An effort to eradicate it may play out like an attempt to squeeze air out of a partially inflated balloon: What disappears from one spot pops up in another.”); Debra Livingston, Police Discretion and the Quality of Life in Public Places: Courts, Communities, and the New Policing, 97 Colum. L. Rev. 551, 593 (1997) (“Limiting the discretion that police exercise on the street simply by demanding specificity in the laws that they enforce is so hopeless . . . . ‘Elimination of discretion at one choice point merely causes the discretion that had been exercised there to migrate elsewhere in the system.’” (quoting Jerry L. Mashaw, Prodelegation: Why Administrators Should Make Political Decisions, 1 J.L. Econ. & Org. 81, 97 (1985))).

[46]Bierschbach & Bibas, supra note 4, at 1470 (footnote omitted); see also Stephanos Bibas, Essay, Transparency and Participation in Criminal Procedure, 81 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 911, 914, 931 (2006) (“On average . . . [professional] insiders are more concerned with and informed about practical constraints . . . . [Lay] [o]utsiders, knowing and caring less about practical obstacles and insiders’ interests, focus on . . . offenders’ just desserts. . . .” They “care about a much wider array of justice concerns than do lawyers, including . . . blameworthiness, and apologies.”).

[47]Jerome Frank, Law and the Modern Mind 178 (Transaction Publishers ed. 2009) (“The constant effort to achieve a stable equilibrium . . . is regressive, infantile, and immature.”); Bowers, Legal Guilt, supra note 5, at 1690–91.

[48]Nussbaum, supra note 13, at 94 (“[T]he equitable person is characterized by a sympathetic understanding of ‘human things.’”); Kahan & Nussbaum, supra note 14, at 287 (observing that an Aristotelian conception of appropriate conduct in a particular context requires “asking what a person of practical wisdom would do and feel in the situation,” not by asking mechanistically what the law commands).

[[49]Bierschbach & Bibas, supra note 4, at 1473; David Garland, Punishment and Modern Society: A Study in Social Theory 1 (1990) (noting that punishment falls short of societal expectations because “we have tried to convert a deeply social issue into a technical task for specialist institutions”).

[50]Stephanos Bibas, The Machinery of Criminal Justice (2012).

[51]Bierschbach & Bibas, supra note 4, at 1483–84 (“No one institutional player should hold all the cards. . . . An outcomes-focused conception of equality bent on centralizing sentencing and reducing discretion is in tension with this checks-and-balances approach.” (footnote omitted)). 

Defending Two Concepts of Discrimination: A Reply to Simons

In the pages of this Law Review, Professor Kenneth Simons kindly pays me the compliment of serious and sustained engagement with, and critique of, my article Two Concepts of Discrimination[1] (hereinafter “Two Concepts”).[2] In what follows, I return the compliment. While I think that Simons offers some important challenges, I argue that the heart of his critique rests on a confusion. In Two Concepts, I argue that there are two distinct ways of understanding the wrong of discrimination that animate equal protection doctrine. On one conception, discrimination is a comparative wrong and on the other, discrimination is a noncomparative (or what I term “independent”) wrong. Professor Simons’s main objection is that he thinks discrimination is always a comparative wrong and thus that my attempt to characterize aspects of the doctrine as resting on the noncomparative conception of discrimination is incoherent. In his view, there are not two concepts of discrimination, only one.

Simons begins by asserting that “[b]y definition, wrongful discrimination refers to unjustified distinctions between persons. How can this wrong be understood as noncomparative? The very basis of the complaint is the claimed injustice of differential treatment.”[3] Simons’s claim that by definition, wrongful discrimination is a claim of unjustified differentiation asserts the very claim that is in dispute. I have offered an account according to which there are two ways of conceiving of the wrong of discrimination, one comparative and one noncomparative. Simons cannot simply define the term “discrimination” such that he is right. This is to win the dispute by fiat rather than argument.

He goes on, in the passage quoted above, to offer a reason. He claims that the fact that complaints of discrimination generally point to the differential treatment shows that discrimination is a comparative wrong. This argument helps me recognize that there are different ways in which one can understand the distinction between a comparative and a noncomparative injustice and that he and I may be calling attention to different facets of that claim.[4] There are (at least) three different ways one might characterize the distinction between comparative and noncomparative justice claims. First, one might be pointing to the structure of the complaint of the person alleging discrimination. Does the complainant, call her A, say: “I got X when B (someone else) got Y; that’s not fair” (the comparative complaint)? Or does the complainant say: “I got X when I should have received Y; that’s not right” (the noncomparative complaint)?

Second, the distinction between comparative and noncomparative claims may refer to what we might call the normative grounding of the claim. In other words, how do we assess A’s treatment? Must we look to see how others are treated in order to determine if A received the treatment she should? If discrimination is a comparative injustice, then we determine if A received the treatment she should by comparing the treatment A received (treatment X) with the treatment accorded to B (treatment Y). In contrast, if discrimination is a noncomparative injustice, we look at the treatment accorded to A (treatment X) and assess if this is the correct way to treat A (without comparing that treatment to the treatment accorded to any real or hypothetical other person). If the permissibility of A’s treatment depends on the comparison with the treatment accorded (or that would be accorded) to B, then the claim is one of comparative justice. If it does not, then it is an independent claim.

Third, both comparative and noncomparative justice claims rely on a substantive conception of justice. When we compare the treatment of A and B, what are we looking to see? In Two Concepts, I suggest that the comparative conception of wrongful discrimination likely relies on a substantive conception of equality. We compare the treatment of A and B and ask if giving A treatment X, when B gets treatment Y, treats A and B as equals. The independent approach focuses only on A and the treatment she received. But in order to know if this is the correct treatment, we must assess it in light of some standard of how A ought to be treated. In Two Concepts, I suggest that this may be an entitlement to (some degree of) freedom or autonomy. The contrast between the comparative and independent conceptions of discrimination may thus refer to the values that underlie each: equality versus freedom, for example.

The existence of three ways of understanding the distinction between comparative and noncomparative conceptions of discrimination reveals the purported disagreement between Professor Simons and me to rest on a confusion. My claim that there are two coherent ways of conceiving of the wrong of discrimination, one comparative and one noncomparative, refers to the second way of understanding that distinction––the version that focuses on the normative grounding of the claim. Simons’s rejection of the noncomparative conception of discrimination refers, in most instances, to either the structure of the complaint (the first version) or to the underlying value (the third version). Let me explain.

When Simons offers the argument that “[t]he very basis of the complaint is the claimed injustice of differential treatment,”[5] he refers to the structure of the complaint offered by the person alleging discrimination. It is true that people point to differential treatment in making a claim of wrongful discrimination. It is for this reason that the noncomparative conception of discrimination feels odd, as I readily acknowledge.[6] In claiming that discrimination can be understood as a noncomparative injustice, I do not assert that this is how people generally frame their complaints. Moreover, Simons concedes that “some scholars and judges do appear to characterize the wrong of discrimination as noncomparative,” so the problem isn’t that it is too bizarre an idea to entertain.[7] In this sense, we both agree that claims of discrimination are usually framed in comparative terms—though some scholars and judges sometimes frame them otherwise. He thinks this fact reveals something important about the “basis” of the claim. I think it might (if discrimination is a comparative wrong) or might not (if it is not). But for Simons to conclude that discrimination can only be seen as a comparative injustice, he must point to more than the manner in which complaints of discrimination are offered.

Simons also sometimes refers to the third way one might draw the distinction between comparative and noncomparative justice claims, that is, the one that refers to the ultimate value at stake. Consider what he says about the right to define one’s gender identity, which I characterize as the noncomparative claim that undergirds some of the Supreme Court’s sex discrimination jurisprudence:

              To be sure, the right to define one’s own gender identity is a right that all citizens enjoy. But a universal right is not necessarily a noncomparative right. If, as in this instance, the rationale for the right is to avoid comparative injustice, then the right should be characterized as comparative.[8]

What makes the universal right to define one’s gender identity comparative, according to Simons, is the fact that its rationale is equality based. But the fact that the underlying value served is equality does not entail that the right should be understood as comparative. To see why, consider the following example. Suppose that there are sentencing guidelines that cabin the discretion of judges in sentencing and that for a particular offense, a judge must sentence the offender (X) to five years. Here the treatment that X should get is determined by the legal rule (and in this example I am supposing that the guidelines operate as more than guidelines).[9] If so, the treatment X should get is set independently of the treatment afforded to others (which makes this a matter of noncomparative justice). However, if we were to ask why we have such guidelines, at least one common justification for them is that by restricting the discretion of judges, we reduce the inequality in sentencing between comparable offenders and often the racial disparity in sentencing. This is a justification that appeals to concerns about equality.

One could, of course, justify sentencing guidelines without reference to equality as well. One might say that guidelines help to ensure that judges hand down the correct sentences. If one believes that judges will, on average, hand down the correct sentences more often when constrained by this rule than when exercising discretion, then the rule better serves (noncomparative) justice.[10] This example shows that the underlying rationale for a policy that makes sentencing a matter of noncomparative justice can be either equality or desert. However, even if the sentencing policy is ultimately grounded in a concern for equality––we might even say a concern with comparative justice more broadly––the policy itself makes sentencing a matter of noncomparative justice.

Now that we see the three different ways in which one could claim that discrimination can be a noncomparative injustice, we can isolate where the disagreement between Professor Simons and myself actually lies. We both acknowledge that claims of wrongful discrimination are generally framed in comparative terms (the structure of the complaint dimension). We also both think that “universal” rights can be justified, ultimately, by appeal to equality (the question of the ultimate value). So, where do we disagree? First, we disagree because I do not think that either the fact that complaints of discrimination are generally framed in comparative terms, or the fact that equality is the underlying value served by identifying an independent right entails that the right is comparative. Rather, I think what really matters to whether a right is comparative or independent is the normative grounding for the claim. In my view, discrimination can be viewed as a noncomparative wrong because determining whether A’s getting treatment X is permissible can be assessed without reference to the treatment accorded to a real or hypothetical B.

The second place in which we may disagree is regarding whether the right that government ignore one’s race and the right to define one’s gender identity are rights whose normative grounding is noncomparative. Does Simons disagree? I am not sure.

Simons acknowledges that if there is a right to define one’s own gender identity, that would be a “universal right,”[11] which means, I would think, that each person is entitled to it simply by virtue of being a person. If so, one has such a right independent of how others are treated. Recall though, Simons thinks that this right is, nevertheless, comparative because the reason for it is based in a concern for equality. Not only does this argument confuse the normative grounding of the right with the ultimate value it serves––as explained above––but it would seem to turn many clearly noncomparative rights into comparative rights.

Consider a right to health care. Suppose one thinks that every human being has a right to access health care. This seems clearly to be a noncomparative right. Yet, one possible reason to support such a right might be that it is equality enhancing. Does the fact that access to health care leads to equality in some dimensions turn this right into a claim of comparative justice? I wouldn’t think so. Of course the proponent of a universal right to health care might ground that right in human needs, irrespective of equality concerns. That is, the right need not be grounded in equality. But so too, a person might defend a right to define one’s gender identity without reference to equality concerns. It might be grounded in the harm to individuals of being forced into a gender identity that feels oppressive or in the autonomy-based right to define one’s identity for oneself more generally.

Perhaps the case of the right to have one’s race ignored better supports Simons’s claim that discrimination claims cannot be articulated as noncomparative rights. In Two Concepts, I use anticlassification doctrine as an important example of an independent understanding of the wrong of discrimination. Why does Simons think it is a nonstarter? The first thing he asks about it is this: “How would this claim arise?”[12] He rightly observes that the claimant frames the claim in comparative terms. The white applicant denied a place at a university focuses on the fact that her race was a factor because she was denied a place while others of other races were admitted. But in Two Concepts, I acknowledge, as I stressed above, that discrimination claims are generally framed in comparative terms but assert that “[a]ccording to the independent approach, the comparison isn’t doing any real work.”[13] Comparison is what makes the treatment salient but not what makes it wrong.

Because Simons ignores the distinction between how the claim is framed and what makes it salient to the complainant, on the one hand, and what makes it wrong, on the other, he misses the way in which the right to have one’s race ignored is a claim to an independent right. He rightly notes that “the principal concern of those who object to affirmative action programs” is that they are denied entry while others are admitted.[14] Still, what makes this treatment wrong, according to the anticlassification theory, is that race plays a role in admissions. This is a claim to an independent, noncomparative right.

Simons is correct to emphasize that characterizing rights as comparative or instead as independent is complex, and to force me to clarify in what sense, exactly, I claim that discrimination can be understood as either a comparative or a noncomparative wrong. Engagement with his critique has allowed me to better understand that I am not referring to the manner in which a complaint arises (the structure of the complaint dimension). Nor am I referring to the underlying value served by either the comparative or noncomparative right (the ultimate value dimension). Instead, I claim that discrimination can be understood as a noncomparative wrong because the normative grounding for the claim can be noncomparative in the following sense: A gets treatment X. She may note that B gets treatment Y, and because Y is better than X, A may be upset. But what makes the treatment that A gets wrong is not the fact that B gets Y when A gets X. What makes the treatment wrong, according to an independent conception of wrongful discrimination, is that A is not treated as she is entitled to be treated.

There is more to say, particularly in response to Simons’s rejection of two of the three implications of the conceptual distinction I articulate. However, as those applications follow from the conceptual distinction, clarifying exactly where we disagree and rebutting his rejection of the noncomparative conception of discrimination should pave the way for a later conversation about the second part of my article. I look forward to continuing the discussion.

 


[1]Deborah Hellman, Two Concepts of Discrimination, 102 Va. L. Rev. 895 (2016).

[2]Kenneth W. Simons, Discrimination Is a Comparative Injustice: A Reply to Hellman, 102 Va. L. Rev. Online 85 (2016).

[3]Id. at 88.

[4]Simons points out that pinpointing the nature of our disagreement “reveal[s] a greater complexity in the structure and justification of comparative rights than first appears.” Id. at 89.

[5]Id. at 88.

[6]I emphasize that this view is “counterintuitive” and thus spend more time developing it than I do the comparative view. Hellman, supra note 1, at 910.

[7]Simons, supra note 2, at 88.

[8]Id. at 93.

[9]The federal sentencing guidelines prior to United States v. Booker, 543 U.S. 220 (2005), operated in just this way. See id. at 233 (“The Guidelines as written, however, are not advisory; they are mandatory and binding on all judges.” (citation omitted)).

[10]See, e.g., Frederick Schauer, Playing by the Rules: A Philosophical Examination of Rule-Based Decision-Making in Law and in Life (1993).

[11]Simons, supra note 2, at 93.

[12]Id. at 89.

[13]Hellman, supra note 1, at 911.

[14]Simons, supra note 2, at 90.

 

Data Privacy and Inmate Recidivism

When one thinks of prison, the concept of privacy does not generally come to mind. Indeed, the Panopticon imagined by English philosopher Jeremy Bentham—a prison designed in such a way that no inmate could be certain whether he was currently being watched—has become reality.[1] While Bentham envisioned a centralized “inspector” with the ability to peer into the prison cells that surrounded him,[2] modern Internet-connected technologies have allowed today’s inspectors to surveil inmates regardless of their physical proximity.

But while the introduction of Internet-connected technologies into correctional facilities has enhanced the surveillance capabilities of the watchers, it has also provided value to the watched. The introduction of video-messaging services, for example, has allowed inmates to communicate with loved ones who are unable to travel to visit in person.[3] Indeed, the private companies that obtain government contracts to introduce these Internet-connected technologies into correctional facilities often argue that their services can reduce recidivism rates by providing inmates with the opportunity to engage in such communication services.[4] A close examination of the privacy policies offered by these correctional contractors, however, reveals how efforts to reduce recidivism rates are undermined.

As this Essay will explain, correctional contractors collect sensitive data about inmates and the loved ones with whom they communicate. If this data is stolen or sold it can result in substantial harm. Allowing mistaken or misleading data to end up in the hands of an employer or would-be creditor, for example, can undermine efforts to successfully integrate former inmates back into society. Similarly, even accurate data that links individuals with their prior criminal acts can result in former inmates facing burdens in credit and labor markets long after they have paid their debt to society. As research continues to examine the cyclical relationship between incarceration and poverty, placing additional burdens on former inmates in credit and labor markets means placing additional burdens on society’s interest in reducing recidivism rates and lifting families out of poverty.[5] The privacy policies currently offered by correctional contractors do not protect against these problems. This Essay therefore calls on the Federal Communications Commission (“FCC”) to correct such harms.

Having recently set out to establish the maximum rates that correctional contractors can charge inmates for telephone services,[6] the FCC is the appropriate entity to regulate the Internet services that these correctional contractors also provide. Indeed, the FCC has already sought comment on “[t]he use, costs and rates of video visitation and other advanced inmate communications . . . and whether these services could be used to circumvent traditional [inmate calling services] rates.”[7] While establishing rate caps for Internet services is an important step, this Essay calls on the FCC to regulate Internet services within correctional facilities on two additional fronts. First, the FCC should prohibit correctional contractors from selling the data they collect to private third parties. Second, the FCC should establish clear liability guidelines holding correctional contractors liable for data breaches.

Part I will examine the current landscape in which these correctional contractors have introduced their services into correctional facilities. Doing so reveals the financial incentives that state and local governments have to grant contracts with inadequate privacy policies, elucidating the need for federal intervention. Part II will then address how current privacy policies offer inmates and their loved ones inadequate protection, and propose how the FCC can act to require increased privacy protections.

I. Landscape

Many correctional facilities now permit inmates to access the Internet.[8] One interest that state and local governments have in doing so is that permitting such access can reduce recidivism rates. Permitting access to online educational tools, for example, can provide inmates with marketable skills they can use to secure stable employment after their release.[9] Similarly, allowing inmates to communicate with loved ones can help foster supportive relationships.[10] Indeed, the FCC has acknowledged that “contact between inmates and their loved ones has been shown to reduce the rate of recidivism.”[11]

State and local governments, however, also have a troubling incentive to introduce these services: Correctional facilities often supplement their budgets with kickback payments based on a correctional contractor’s profits.[12] Indeed, these payments appear to be so substantial that some correctional contractors have sued to stop the implementation of the FCC’s rate caps on telephone services, arguing that the caps are too low to allow the contractors “to recoup the . . . payments that they are contractually obligated to make [to correctional facilities].”[13] Because correctional contractors can increase their profits by selling their customers’ data, correctional facilities have the financial incentive to approve privacy policies that allow for such sales, thus undermining efforts to reduce recidivism rates. Part I will address this financial incentive in greater detail and outline the authority under which the FCC can regulate this relationship.

A. Current Legal Framework

Since Justice Harlan’s announcement in Katz v. United States that the Fourth Amendment protects an individual’s “reasonable expectation of privacy,”[14] the Fourth Amendment has offered a constitutional grounding for privacy protections. As time would reveal, however, this constitutional grounding was rather unsteady, and the Court has since resorted to crafting an intricate web of context-specific rules to define “reasonable expectation of privacy.”[15] One such rule addresses how the Fourth Amendment applies in correctional facilities. In Hudson v. Palmer the Court held that inmates have no “reasonable expectation of privacy in [their] prison cell entitling [them] to the protection of the Fourth Amendment against unreasonable searches and seizures.”[16]

As the Court made clear in Palmer, correctional facilities are not typically thought of as privacy havens, nor should they be. The Court in Palmer, however, did not declare that inmates have no legitimate interest in privacy. Instead, the Court simply held that any privacy interest that an inmate might have would need to be derived from a source other than the Fourth Amendment. This Essay therefore suggests a regulatory framework designed to offer privacy protections where the Fourth Amendment fails to do so.

B. The Need for Federal Regulation and the FCC’s Authority

As state and local budgets came under greater scrutiny during the Great Recession, correctional facilities increasingly sought new sources of funding.[17] Correctional contractors provided one such source, offering to pay correctional facilities a portion of their profits through kickback payments.[18] These kickback payments led state and local governments to develop a financial incentive that directly conflicts with the interests of inmates and their loved ones, as well as society’s long-term interest in reducing recidivism rates. This conflict has resulted in a need for federal action, a need that the FCC began to fulfill in October 2015 when it set out to cap the rates at which correctional contractors can charge for telephone services.[19] The FCC should similarly regulate Internet services—services often provided by the same companies that provide telephone services in correctional facilities.[20]

Though fundamental principles of federalism require a pragmatic approach to considering federal regulation of state correctional systems, Internet services are hardly an intrastate matter. Not only do the communications themselves travel across state boundaries, the effects on inmates are not contained within the state in which inmates are incarcerated. As the federal agency tasked with regulating Internet service providers, the FCC has the authority to regulate Internet services provided by correctional contractors. The FCC’s authority to do so derives primarily from Section 706 of the Telecommunications Act, which requires the FCC to “encourage the deployment . . . of advanced telecommunications capability to all Americans.”[21] The FCC relied on Section 706 in promulgating rules regarding “net neutrality,” a principle of Internet governance that requires Internet service providers to handle Internet traffic similarly regardless of its source.[22] In Verizon v. FCC, the U.S. Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit largely agreed with the FCC’s interpretation of Section 706.[23]

Section 222 of the Communications Act also provides the FCC with the authority to enforce privacy standards.[24] Section 222 requires “[e]very telecommunications carrier . . . to protect the confidentiality of proprietary information of, and relating to, . . . customers.”[25] The FCC recently invoked its authority under Section 222 when requiring one Internet service provider to pay a substantial civil penalty and to implement data security safeguards in the aftermath of a data breach.[26]

II. Data Breaches and Selling to Third Parties

By monitoring inmate communications, correctional contractors claim that their proprietary software can help correctional facilities analyze communications to “expose suspicious patterns.”[27] While the government may have a legitimate interest in contracting with correctional contractors to perform these services, Part II will examine the type of data these contractors collect, and how sharing this data with private third parties—whether it be involuntarily through a data breach, or through a voluntary transaction—can undermine efforts to reduce recidivism rates.

A. What Correctional Contractors Collect

Correctional contractors collect a wide range of data. One correctional contractor, for example, collects the “date of birth, [and] social security number” of its customers.[28] Another correctional contractor collects “[c]ontact information such as name, address, telephone number or email address,” as well as “[c]redit/[d]ebit card information,” and “the Internet Protocol (IP) address used to connect [a] computer or any internet-accessible device to the internet as well as login and password information.”[29] Data pertaining to the content of communications is also collected, with one correctional contractor stating it reserves “the right to access, read, preserve, and disclose any information” sent through their emailing service,[30] as well as the “right to view, record, preserve, and disclose any information” contained in communications sent through its video-messaging service.[31]

Not only do correctional contractors collect this data about inmates, they also collect data about loved ones outside of correctional facilities. Indeed, correctional contractors are “able to identify the location of [a loved one’s] mobile device,” and may share “location information . . . with correctional facilities or other law enforcement personnel upon their request.”[32] A third correctional contractor notes that they record “the websites . . . visit[ed] before or after” loved ones use their service.[33]

Collecting this type of sensitive and valuable data not only makes correctional contractors a target for hackers, it also means that these contractors have data that third parties are willing to pay for.[34] As Section II.B illustrates, although sharing this data with private third parties can undermine efforts to reduce recidivism rates, correctional contractors are currently free to do so.

B. Current Privacy Policies Are Inadequate

Correctional contractors can share the data they collect about inmates and their loved ones quite freely.  One correctional contractor’s privacy policy states that “[w]e may use information collected from or about you . . . to send you . . . promotional materials from our marketing partners and other third parties; to deliver targeted display advertisements . . . [and] for any other business or marketing purposes that are not inconsistent with the terms of this Privacy Statement.”[35] Another correctional contractor notes that they “do not sell, trade, or otherwise transfer to outside parties [customer’s] personally identifiable information,” except with “trusted third parties who assist [them] in . . . conducting [their] business.”[36] Such language is opaque, and might be entirely circular if the correctional contractor’s very “business” includes selling customer data in the first place. The appropriate policy question to ask, however, is not whether a specific correctional contractor is currently selling customer data, but whether correctional contractors should be in the position to freely do so in the first place. Current market conditions leave correctional contractors in such a position—with some correctional facilities beginning to replace in-person visitation hours with video-messaging services.[37]

This growing trend to replace in-person visitation hours with video-messaging services leaves inmates and their loved ones with little choice but to agree to the privacy policies offered by correctional contractors.[38] These families are often poverty-stricken, a fact raised in support of the FCC’s objective to establish rate caps for telephone services.[39] Similar to how charging poverty-stricken families exorbitant prices for telephone services can increase their financial difficulties, requiring these same families to agree to the privacy policies currently offered by correctional contractors can create additional burdens on them in credit and labor markets. These burdens can develop as a result of sharing either inaccurate or accurate data.

Data collected by correctional contractors can be inaccurate as a result of at least two issues. First, data might simply be incorrectly handled or labeled. This is of increased concern when it comes to data collected in jails, where inaccuracies may result in inmates being unjustly associated with crimes they have not been convicted of.

Second, conclusions drawn from underlying data can be inaccurate. This might result from the content of communications between inmates and their loved ones containing inaccuracies, or from questionable analysis performed after collection. One correctional contractor, for example, advertises that its product “enables correctional facilities to easily share with other facilities . . . to help find common phone numbers, expose larger gang networks, and generally provide the ‘big picture’ of the communications and interactions among inmates and their associates.”[40] If an inaccurate conclusion is shared with third parties, it can unjustly stigmatize inmates in credit and labor markets. For example, inaccurately concluding that an inmate is associated with gang networks can make it more difficult for them to secure employment after their release.[41]

Consider the example of a job applicant in Arkansas who had incorrect data shared about her indicating that she was charged with the “intent to sell and manufacture methamphetamines.”[42] Not only did this data result in her being denied employment, it prevented her from renting an apartment and even from obtaining credit to purchase a dishwashing machine.[43] Although the company that originally misreported this data corrected their records, the data had already been sold to other companies who “did not necessarily follow suit.”[44] As more businesses turn to “data-driven” solutions, the market in which data is sold has become increasingly complex—with a correction of one company’s records not necessarily resulting in a correction of the records held by any number of companies that have since obtained derivative copies of the underlying data.[45] Sharing this type of sensitive data with employers, creditors, and landlords can leave former inmates unable to successfully integrate back into society.[46]

While inaccurate data presents one set of issues, additional issues arise even when accurate data is shared about a former inmate.[47] By creating an electronic record linking a former inmate with their incarceration, former inmates can find it increasingly difficult to distance themselves from the prior criminal acts for which they have already been punished.[48] This is of particular concern in light of the difficulties involved in unraveling the complex web of companies that sell and resell data. While some states have instituted “ban the box” laws that prohibit employers from inquiring into a job applicant’s criminal record until later in the hiring process,[49] such laws are rendered ineffective where a simple Google search can reveal such information, or where private databases that cater to employers use such information as part of the database’s underlying score of job applicants.[50] One must question the desirability of a system where former inmates are punished long after they have formally served their sentence, especially where the government has an interest in reducing the likelihood that such prolonged punishment occurs. In part as a response to this type of problem, the Court of Justice of the European Union held that E.U. citizens have a right to request that search engines remove links about them that are inaccurate or even “irrelevant.”[51]

This “right to be forgotten” requires search engines to “assess deletion requests on a case-by-case basis” to determine if a given link must be removed under E.U. law.[52] While such a regime might prevent a former inmate from being continually denied credit and employment opportunities, the First Amendment likely prohibits U.S courts from finding a similar right.[53] The FCC, however, is able to limit a correctional contractor’s ability to sell this data as a precondition to being awarded a government contract. Section II.C will outline how the FCC should establish such a precondition.

C. How the FCC Can Protect Privacy

Just as the FCC established boundaries within which companies may contract with correctional facilities to provide telephone services, the FCC should establish similar boundaries regarding Internet services. In addition to establishing rate caps for Internet services, the FCC should regulate these services on two additional fronts.

First, the FCC should prohibit correctional contractors from selling the data they collect from inmates and their loved ones to private third parties. While it is appropriate to require inmates and their loved ones to agree to a reasonable degree of monitoring by law enforcement to ensure that Internet services are not used for nefarious communications, selling this data to private third parties unnecessarily undermines efforts to reduce recidivism rates by placing substantial burdens on former inmates in credit and labor markets. Regardless of the extent to which selling customer data is already a major component of a correctional contractor’s business model, the FCC should act now to curtail it. While selling customer data may be a valuable perk of providing Internet services within correctional facilities, it is a perk that must be trumped by efforts to successfully integrate former inmates back into society.

Second, the FCC should make clear that correctional contractors will be held financially liable for data breaches. Just as selling data can place substantial burdens on former inmates in credit and labor markets, these same burdens can result where data is shared as a result of a data breach. Earlier in 2015 the FCC entered into a consent agreement with one Internet service provider—AT&T—after customers’ social security numbers were leaked.[54] Under the consent agreement, AT&T was required to “pay a civil penalty of $25,000,000 and develop and implement a compliance plan to . . . protect consumers against similar data breaches in the future.”[55] The FCC should make it clear that correctional contractors would face similar liability in the wake of a data breach.

By making it clear that correctional contractors will be held liable in the wake of a data breach, the FCC can place correctional contractors on notice of the significant impact that the data they collect can have on society’s interest in reducing recidivism rates.[56] As the original collectors of the data, placing liability on correctional contractors is appropriate in light of the difficulties involved in tracing how data is repackaged and shared once it is originally leaked. By establishing clear liability guidelines, the FCC can provide correctional contractors with an incentive to appropriately protect the sensitive data they collect, and ensure that the costs of a data breach are not disproportionately placed on former inmates and their loved ones.

Conclusion

While correctional contractors provide a valuable service that can help reduce recidivism rates, the privacy policies they currently offer undermine that goal. Sharing sensitive data about inmates and their loved ones—whether it be involuntarily through a data breach, or through a voluntary transaction—illustrates one way these privacy policies fall short. The FCC can correct this issue by prohibiting correctional contractors from selling the data they collect to private third parties, and by establishing clear liability guidelines for data breaches.

 


[1]Thomas McMullan, What Does the Panopticon Mean in the Age of Digital Surveillance?, Guardian (July 23, 2015), http://www.theguardian.com/t‌echnology/2015/jul/23/pano‌pticon-digital-surveillance-jeremy-bentham [https://perma.cc/435Q-6BVF].

[2]Jeremy Bentham, Panopticon: Or, the Inspection-House 4–5 (Dublin, Thomas Byrne 1791).

[3]See, e.g., Emily Green, Captive Consumers: Corporations Reap Big Profits on Inmate Finances, Video Visitation in Multnomah County, Street Roots News (Jan. 6, 2015), http://news.streetroots.org/2015/01/06/captive-consumers-reap-big-profits-inmate-finances-video-visitations [https://perma.cc/G687-N9ET].

[4]Securus Technologies, Inc. to Acquire JPay Inc., PR Newswire (Apr. 14, 2015, 11:30 AM), htt‌p://www.prnewswire.com/news-releases/securus-technologies-inc-to-acquire-jpay-i‌nc-300065531.html [https://perma.cc/J98A-STHM].

[5]See Sasha Abramsky, Toxic Persons, Slate (Oct. 8, 2010, 7:34 AM), http://ww‌w.slat‌e.c‌o‌m/articles/news_and_politics/jurisprudence/2010/10/toxic_persons.html [htt‌ps://p‌erm‌a.c‌c‌/S‌D7J-CVP6].

[6]Jon Brodkin, FCC Will Let Jails Charge Inmates More for Phone Calls, Ars Technica (July 18, 2016, 12:55 PM), http://arstechnica.com/tech-policy/2016/07/fcc-will-let-jails-char‌ge-inmates-more-for-phone-calls/ [https://perma.cc/2ZUX-PQZV].

[7]Press Release, FCC, FCC Takes Next Big Steps in Reducing Inmate Calling Rates (Oct. 22, 2015), https://apps.fcc.gov/edocs_public/attachmatch/DOC-335984A1.pdf [https://perm‌a.cc/C2R4-8R6B].

[8]Ben Branstetter, The Case for Internet Access in Prison, Wash. Post (Feb. 9, 2015), https://www.washingtonpost.com/news/the-intersect/wp/2015/02/09/the-case-for-internet-ac‌cess-in-prisons/ [https://perma.cc/M6KV-YEKE].

[9]Anne Field, Startup’s Education Platform for Curbing Recidivism Launches Pilot in Philly Prison, Forbes, Oct. 31, 2014, http://www.forbes.com/sites/annefield/2‌014/10/31/sta‌rtups-education-platform-for-curbing-recidivism-launches-pilot-in-philly-prison/ [https://p‌er‌ma.cc/76NH-9X5M].

[10]Margaret diZerega & Sandra Villalobos Agudelo, Vera Inst. of Justice, Piloting a Tool for Reentry: A Promising Approach to Engaging Family Members 4 (2011), http://www.vera.org/sites/default/files/resources/downloads/Piloting-a-Tool-for-Reentry-Updated.pdf [https://perma.cc/5NX6-U6SY].

[11]Press Release, FCC, supra note 7.

[12]Stephanie Clifford & Jessica Silver-Greenberg, In Prisons, Sky-High Phone Rates and Money Transfer Fees, N.Y. Times (June 26, 2014), http://www.nytim‌es.c‌om/20‌14/‌06/27/business/in-prisons-sky-high-phone-rates-and-money-transfer-fees.html?_r=0 [http‌s://‌perma.cc/6MCM-PPUA].

[13]Motion of Global Tel*Link for Partial Stay Pending Judicial Review at 9, Global Tel*Link v. FCC (D.C. Cir. 2016) (No. 15-1461), http://cdn.arstechnica.net/wp-con‌tent/up‌loads/2016/03/prison-phone-stay-petition.pdf [https://perma.cc/KX5L-898P].

[14]389 U.S. 347, 360 (1967) (Harlan, J., concurring).

[15]Orin S. Kerr, An Equilibrium-Adjustment Theory of the Fourth Amendment, 125 Harv. L. Rev. 476, 479–80 (2011).

[16]468 U.S. 517, 519 (1984).

[17]Patrice A. Fulcher, The Double-Edged Sword of Prison Video Visitation: Claiming to Keep Families Together While Furthering the Aims of the Prison Industrial Complex, 9 Fla. A&M U. L. Rev. 83, 85–87 (2013).

[18]Clifford & Silver-Greenberg, supra note 12.

[19]Press Release, FCC, supra note 7.

[20]Matt Stroud & Joshua Brustein, Expensive ‘Prison Skype’ Is Squeezing Out In-Person Visitation, Bloomberg News (Apr. 27, 2015, 11:07 AM), http://www.bloomb‌erg.c‌om/n‌ews/a‌rticles/2015-04-27/expensive-prison-skype-is-squeezing-out-in-person-visitation [http‌s://per‌ma.cc/44FP-X898].

[21]47 U.S.C. § 1302(a) (2012).

[22]Protecting and Promoting the Open Internet, 80 Fed. Reg. 19,738, 19,738 (Apr. 13, 2015) (to be codified at 47 C.F.R. pts. 1, 8, 20).

[23]740 F.3d 623, 628 (D.C. Cir. 2014).

[24]47 U.S.C. § 222 (2012).

[25]Id. § 222(a).

[26]Sam Pfeifle, FCC Fines AT&T $25m for Data Privacy Lapse; Who Will Be Next?, Int’l Ass’n Privacy Prof.: The Privacy Advisor (Apr. 9, 2015), https://iapp.org/news/a/fcc-fines-at-who-will-be-next/ [https://perma.cc/7QDY-5X5X].

[27]See, e.g., GTL Inmate Data Analysis, GTL, http://www.gtl.net/correctional-facility-services/investigative-solutions/data-analysis/ [https://perma.cc/M7FY-VJVW].

[28]Privacy Policy, Securus, https://securustech.net/privacy [https://perma.cc/CP87-6JD7].

[29]Privacy Policy, JPay, http://www.jpay.com/LegalAgreementsOut.aspx [https://perm‌a.cc/M8DM-FKCA].

[30]Email Terms of Service, JPay, http://www.jpay.com/LegalAgreementsOut.aspx [ht‌tp‌s://perma.cc/M8DM-FKCA].

[31]Video Visitation Terms of Service, JPay, http://www.jpay.com/L‌egalA‌greemen‌tsO‌ut.aspx [https://perma.cc/M8DM-FKCA].

[32]Global Tel*Link Corp., Privacy Statement 3, 5 (2015), http://www.gtl.net/wp-conte‌nt/up‌loads/2015/04/GTL%20NET%20-%20Privacy%20Statement%20-%20Final%20-%20%‌20‌0‌3-30-15.pdf [https://perma.cc/96LH-C8BT].

[33]Id. at 2.

[34]John W. Bagby, Balancing the Public Policy Drivers in the Tension Between Privacy and Security in 3 Cyber Crime: Concepts, Methodologies, Tools and Applications 1441, 1451 (Info. Res. Mgmt. Ass’n ed., 2012).

[35]Global Tel*Link Corp., supra note 32, at 4–5.

[36]General Terms and Conditions Including Privacy Policy, Product Terms and Conditions, and Mobile Terms and Conditions, Securus, https://securustech.net/terms-and-condi‌tion‌s#privacy [https://perma.cc/B6LX-VGXS].

[37]Stroud & Brunstein, supra note 20.

[38]Id.

[39]Ahiza Garcia, $14 a Minute? Pricey Prison Phone Calls Capped by FCC, CNN Money (Oct. 23, 2015, 9:54 AM), http://money.cnn.com/2015/10/23/news/fcc-prison-phone-call-ra‌t‌es/ [https://perma.cc/993Y-9RTF].

[40]GTL Inmate Data Analysis, supra note 27.

[41]See Will Hobson, Police Gang Lists Can Have Life-Long Impacts and are Questioned by Legal Experts, Tampa Bay Times (Sept. 15, 2012, 7:08 PM), http://www.ta‌mpa‌bay.com/news/publicsafety/crime/police-gang-lists-can-have-life-long-im‌pacts-and-are-ques‌tioned-by-legal/1251855 [https://perma.cc/BAL7-J72G].

[42]Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society 33 (2015) (internal quotation marks omitted).

[43]Id.

[44]Id.

[45]See Andrew Guthrie Ferguson, Big Data and Predictive Reasonable Suspicion, 163 Univ. Pa. L. Rev. 327, 399–400 (2015).

[46]See Pasquale, supra note 42, at 22, 33–34 (describing how false claims regarding criminal history can negatively affect job applicants).

[47]See Jenny Roberts, Expunging America’s Rap Sheet in the Information Age, 2015 Wis. L. Rev. 321, 341–42.

[48]See Laura Sullivan, Life After ‘Life’: Aging Inmates Struggling for Redemption, NPR (June 4, 2014), http://www.npr.org/2014/06/04/317055077/life-after-life-aging-inmates-stru‌ggle-for-redemption [https://perma.cc/X6SQ-4ZRU] (“Since he’s been out, Huckleberry has found a couple of jobs, including one at a car dealership. But they fired him when they found out he’s a felon.”).

[49]Reid Wilson, Georgia the Latest State to ‘Ban the Box’ in Hiring Practices, Wash. Post (Feb. 24, 2015), https://www.washingtonpost.com/blogs/govbeat/wp/2015/02/24/georgia-th‌e‌-latest-state-to-ban-the-box-in-hiring-practices/ [https://perma.cc/QGH2-AF9W].

[50]See Stephanie Clifford & Jessica Silver-Greenberg, Retailers Track Employee Thefts in Vast Databases, N.Y. Times (Apr. 2, 2013), http://www.nytimes.com/20‌13/04‌/03/b‌usine‌ss/retailers-use-databases-to-track-worker-thefts.html [https://perma.cc/VEK9-UKCQ].

[51]Case C-131/12, Google Spain SL v. Agencia Española de Protección de Datos (May 13, 2014), http://curia.europa.eu/juris/docum‌ent/document_print.jsf?do‌clang=EN‌&text&pageIn‌dex=0&part=1&mode=DOC&docid=152065&occ=first&dir&cid=437838 [https://perma‌.cc/‌4SL7-H3LJ].

[52]European Comm’n, Factsheet on the “Right to be Forgotten” Ruling (C-131/12), http://ec.europa.eu/justice/data-protection/files/factsheets/factsheet_data_protection_en.pdf [https://perma.cc/9KTZ-RXNZ].

[53]Jeffrey Rosen, The Right to be Forgotten, 64 Stan. L. Rev. Online 88, 88 (2012).

[54]Pfeifle, supra note 26.

[55]AT&T Servs., Inc., 30 FCC Rcd. 2808 (2015).

[56]See, e.g., Danielle Keats Citron, Reservoirs of Danger: The Evolution of Public and Private Law at the Dawn of the Information Age, 80 S. Cal. L. Rev. 241, 264–67 (2007).